INTRODUCTORY
NOTE
During the course
of my undergraduate studies, I have found myself wavering between two mindsets,
roughly characterized as the ÒuniversalistÓ and the Òskeptic.Ó The universalist
aesthetician wishes a universal law through which we may interpret
the artistic value of any given art object. He is sick and tired of people
degrading the music he likes and wants something to appeal to above mere
opinion. The skeptic postmodernist sees this desire as a ruseÑa desperate last-ditch
attempt to imbue value into a world of contingencies and relativisms. He knows
that all we have is our opinion of music, and that ultimately, we arenÕt even in
control of our own tastes. There is simply the endless parade of styles and
fashions that brainwash us with speed and repetition, dulling our senses.
This thesis, as a
response to this internal dilemma, is a thought experiment designed to overcome
this dichotomy, and present it as a true dialectic. We will have access to the
musical works that the critic has access to, and also to his bag of critical
maneuvers. Many of these maneuvers take cultural relativism into account. But
in my eyes, there is a loftier goal for the contemporary critic. It is the
desire to posit a real artistic value that gets around the universal claims
of a Kantian or formalist critic of the past. For, although these methods of
interrogating artistic practice are unfortunately chauvinistic, they strongly
reveal the real purpose of the critical endeavorÑthat is, to explain the real
value of art in our society. And I fear that the farther we plunge into a
deconstruction and fragmentation of institutional values, the less capable it
will be to defend artistic endeavors at all in future generations.
Therefore, in the
following three chapters, I will take the reader through a dialectic. In the
first chapter, I will tow the postmodernist line, beginning with Foucault and
Canon, showing the inevitable problem of delimiting music with critical
language, as critique never exhausts the possibilities for understanding music (and
the myriad formulas that the postmodernist presents). In my critique of
formalism, I will focus on Heinrich SchenkerÕs hierarchical analyses, and a
critique of Modernist formulations of universalism, in the form of Theodor
AdornoÕs writings. I will argue, following from FoucaultÕs theories of canon
formation, that when we lift the veil of limited institutional value, all music
seems to coexist in a plurality.
After a critique of formalism, I will
present, in the second chapter, a sampling of special cases of contemporary
music, including sample-based music, which call out for a new manner of
analysis. What do I mean by this? Pieces such as the Plunderphonics works by
John Oswald, as well as music by composers who straddle the interface between
ÒpopularÓ and ÒseriousÓ music often challenge presuppositions about musical
style which challenge notions of musical autonomy. However, we must utilize some critical
understanding of this music if we are to reveal its value.
I will thus, in the
third chapter, present the groundwork for a critical understanding of music
that I call music-as-discourse. This model, in which I liken music to language, with
both a stylistic and contextual level of meaning, arises from my understanding
of Rose SubotnikÕs critique of formalism, and the possibilities it holds for
both sample-based music, and Foucaultian discourse. Music-as-discourse has us perceive
music as a series of ÒlinguisticÓ statements in historical sequence rather than
simply the canonical referent of music criticism. This, I believe, relieves
sample-based music from some of the problems it poses to traditional musical
discourse. The discourse, which has simply represented music (which is viewed
as essentially non-linguistic), with critical language, has set music
and musical discourse at odds, and led to the ÒproblemsÓ of the Modern.
In the first
chapter, I will simply consider the practice of musical
criticism, as it has occurred up through the mid-20th century as modernism, and
show how a universalist critical thread often prevents us from viewing music in
any way that concedes the plurality and multiplicity of musicÕs place in
contemporary culture.
CHAPTER
ONE: FORMALISM AND ITS DISCONTENTS
A Foucaultian Set-up
Things
change. And observing the material output of human culture can reveal changes
in the structures of knowledge and the context for new innovations and
conceptions. An investigation into artistic practice, and a holistic,
humanistic, and philosophical application of the information gathered, can help
shed light on the way we represent the world by revealing the
dynamic structures that shape our world and our representations of
it. And like varieties of
expression, there are many critical applications we may then extrapolate from
the patterns and progressions we may discover. Hegel observed changes in our
structures of knowledge, and outlined a historical evolution from a focus on
the structures of religion to the structures of philosophy. But if, in some
terrifying nightmarish future, the works of the great philosophers, artists,
and theologians were all forgotten, would our world still be recognizable, and
could we still progress to HegelÕs end-point? For although the existence of an a priori artistic
consciousness is too great a reduction, it is certain that our world views are
predicated on a rich cultural memory observable in the man-made
world. Although many of our greatest artistic, philosophical, and religious
concerns have not changed drastically over the course of human history, it is
certain that our world has changed. Above all, I believe that what has changed is
the form of knowledge, and what counts as real knowledge, which grounds the
possibility of knowledge at all. In science, these may be the conditions by
which we understand statements about the world to be factual. Likewise, in
artistic practice, the meaning of our artistic products and processes are what
is at stake.
Due
to the normalizing day-to-day experience of the world, the conventions of culture,
and the continuity of language, the ultimate contingency of our cultural
prejudices and tastes are often forgotten until the next great change, or
reevaluation of the culture. We take our artistic sensibilities for granted,
but they are intrinsic to the process of reflection. In his book The
Archaeology of Knowledge, Michel Foucault outlines a possible way of
addressing the changes of culture that pollute our understanding of the process
of discourse. He divides discourse (that is, any
group of statements that belongs to a single system of formation) into a series
of types of discursive statements, which may have the appearance of order and
continuity, but are ultimately incompatible and distinctÑsucceeding one
another, intervening on one another, and perhaps coexisting, but never forming
a true continuity. Of course, it is difficult to determine what
constitutes a Òsingle system of formation.Ó Generally, one of the side effects
of an ever-expanding culture is the fragmentation of disciplines into sub-disciplines
and thus, the existence of a dynamic power structure that handles every aspect
of knowledge. In the Archaeology of Knowledge, Foucault sets
forth the canon and the commentary as ways of
understanding the conditioning of our knowledge. The canon is the body of
institutional beliefs that are held fast as the basis of disciplines, and more
generally, civilization itself. For instance, there is a general understanding
that Western civilization is grounded on knowledge of the Bible and the works
of the Greek philosophers. These are the canon, the book underpinning our
society. Likewise, sociology has the works of Weber, Marx, and Mill. Music has
treatises of harmony, and critical writings as well as the music of the Ògreat
composers.Ó How does this reification of certain ideas occur? According to
Foucault, this is achieved through the discursive patterns of commentaryÑthe
invisible, though genuine, history of thought that has privileged one belief
over another due to the Nietzchean will of the society. Not simply the work of
individual tyrants, canon is slowly built through the natural processes of
societal change from one generation to the next. Choices are made, and they
quickly accumulate validity. However, because of the historical necessity of
this process, it is revealed to be pragmatic, and rarely in the true common
interest (whatever that would look like). Musical cultureÕs accumulation of
narratives about the greatness of the composers is only the commentary provided
by individuals, but held in high esteem, in order to maintain the discipline of
music.
But
one can never really know the truth about any given discipline. In fact,
new disciplines emerge due to the intrinsic discontinuities of discursive
statements. For instance, in Madness and Civilization, Foucault
reveals the problem of attempting to combine radically incompatible ideas of
ÒothernessÓ with the single label of madness. For Foucault,
the individual traditions and explanations that we attribute to changing
understandings of madness do not, upon close inspection, clearly belong to a
single, growing body of knowledge about Òmadness,Ó stemming from objective,
scientific facts. Rather, what we label schizophrenia, for example,
cannot be understood as a clarification of earlier forms of ÒmadnessÓ such
as dementia. In one century, the fool was seen as a religious symbol; in another, the
mentally ill as patients for the psychologist. The dynamic power structures
that circle and delimit the discourse only have the scrutiny of authority in
common.
For
Foucault, this is simply the way that language (and the linguistic world)
works, and one must concede a kind of epistemological dead-end, especially as
the discourse of civilization grows and multiplies. Foucault believed that the
fragmentation of knowledge into the disciplines of culture creates a hierarchy
of control. And although Foucault tends to focus on issues revolving around the
infringement of personal freedoms (the construction of madness in Madness
and Civilization and sexuality in The History of Sexuality), such a
discursive view can be used to view any system of formation. In some ways, art
is even more interesting in this respect, because the ÒpurposeÓ of art is so
tied up with the preconceived views of societal Òcommon knowledge.Ó
In a na•ve sense, I take this to mean
that if one wants to ground some ideal Òart-itself,Ó it would consist of
everything ever said about the topic, and everything every considered ÒartÓ per
se. The practical problem with this noumenal object is that as we begin to
unwind the discourse, the notion of art itself begins to disappear. The canon, as it were,
bolstered by the perceived validity of the commentary, can no longer be
seen as valid as the commentary is systematically deconstructed.
Critical
musicology has admitted a kind of parallel to FoucaultÕs notions of contingency
in the musical discourse. That is, the critical understanding of music, which
tends to rely on fixed ÒaxiomsÓ that treat music as a kind of science or math,
or as a stable set of intrinsic signifiers, may not be so simply understood.
New Musicologists, such as Susan McClary, attempt to show that the conventions
that govern most Western music also play a semiotic role, emulating underlying
critical worldviews. The governing notions of tonality that underpin most
conventional Western music rely on a presupposition of the rationality the
tonal system suggests.
My
methods involve paying attention to semiotics, narrativity, genre, reception
history, and cultural theory. Rather than protecting music as a sublimely
meaningless activity that has managed to escape social signification,
I insist on treating it as a medium that participates in social formation
by influencing the ways we perceive our feelings, our bodies, our
desires, our very subjectivitiesÑeven if it does so surreptitiously, without
most of us knowing how.[1]
So,
for McClary it is not enough that the music of Beethoven is beautiful, or that
it utilizes large-scale tonal organization. According to McClary, BeethovenÕs
music presents a violently rational masculinity, with its jarringly propulsive
rhythms and triumphant reassertions of the tonic. For some contextualists,
tonality itself is a structure that represents a critical worldview of
Enlightenment rationality, and therefore the meaning of a classical piece is
not simply the organization of the musical material, but the cultural
significance of that organization. McClary asserts that classical music is
ÒaboutÓ a Òsuccession of hierarchically related harmonies [animating] the
moment-to-moment activity, producing both coherence and a sense of
spontaneity.Ó They are Òdynamic, progressive, rational, and driven by
mechanisms that arouse and eventually satisfy desire.Ó[2]
The
contexutalist approach to music criticism can be a bit subjective and
opinionated, but this subjectivity itself reveals a problem for the canon. It
reveals the tendency to see music as possibly referential, and certainly not
formally inscrutable. With a contextual understanding of music, it is difficult
to show the great difference between Òpure musicÓ and Òprogrammatic music.Ó All
music becomes open to a new historical and critical understanding when we are
willing to observe traits in musical scholarship as strikingly similar to
FoucaultÕs theories of discourse.
For
instance, it is clear that music has an apparent continuity, but also a discontinuity. The division
between High and Low reveals such a conflict. Although there is a historical,
stylistic dialogue between the classical tradition and the music of the volk from the
Renaissance through Liszt and Bart—k, the significance of these connections has
been covered up by the institutional value of authorship. Like today, when
Òfolk singersÓ copyright arrangements of century-old tunes[3],
the composerÕs creation of a piece that incorporates peasant melodies tends to
respect the composerÕs brilliant uses of these melodies over the melodies
themselves, or their anonymous sources. And so, there is continuity, in the
sense that a classical piano piece may derive its scales, say, from peasant
music, but there is a discontinuity in the way the commentary presents this
connection. There is no mistaking a band of gypsy musicians from the Berliner
Philharmoniker. And there are countless other examples. For instance, there is
the attempt to squeeze a particular composer or piece into a designated place
in the canon. Is Ravel really an impressionist? Does Mahler
really write symphonies?
The
notion of a stable musical aesthetics has been tenuous ever since the first commentators
posited such a system. And musical practice has been and
continues to survive even when it goes against the theoretical bases that
explain music or justify its value or validity. What should be Òuniversal
truthsÓ are always revealed to be simply possibilities that are taken up for
one reason or another. And this is easiest to see the further back we look.
While
the Greeks or Medievals did talk about their music, and even formulated theoretical
treatises, they often addressed the subject in vague, esoteric, and
quasi-religious ways. When the Greeks discussed Òthe modes,Ó they did so by
appealing to the Òemotional,Ó or expressive ability of music, primarily through
the use of metaphor.
...the
musical modes differ essentially from one another, and those
who
hear them are different affected by each. Some of them make men
sad and grave,
like the so-called Mixolydian, others enfeeble the mind, like the relaxed
modes, another, again, produces a moderate and settled
temper,
which appears to be the peculiar affect of the Dorian; the
Phrygian
inspires enthusiasm.[4]
These
were their contexts for understanding music, and their text about music reveals
canonical expectations similar to later formalism, not because they said the
same things about how music ought to be, but because of the similar value they gave
to their thoughts about the meaning and purpose of music.
Even
later, this kind of cultural relativism is apparent. Daniel Leech-Wilkinson
argues in The Modern Invention of Medieval Music that most of the
conventions relied upon in resurgent performance of this musical period (and
our greatest knowledge of this music comes from the interest in ÒauthenticityÓ)
are based on conjecture and the historical barrier of the later musical a
priori.
Even
on historical grounds it must be clear that there is no possibility
of
adequately reconstructing such a view of a musical work as might have
held
by the most educated and perceptive musicians of its time. Such a
view,
were it available, might still be open to substantial amplification by
a
similarly expert musician of a succeeding generation, able to see the
period
in question in its larger context. And ultimately, however much we
may
be able to recapture of a period viewÑusing such evidence as
notation,
theory treatises, literary sources and archivesÑwhat we then
see in the music
has still to be expressed in terms which make sense to us. Thus analyses of
surviving works, while taking careful account of what
we
know of period techniques, have to proceed from, and to seek to
explain,
what we currently see and hear in the music. There is no other
view
available to us.[5]
However,
earlier musical discourses reveal more than a kind of cultural relativism. They
show that the critical understandings of one period do not even exhaust the
musical practices of that period. Like today, ancient music treatises attempted
to streamline and translate general practice in order to educate and put forth
solutions to problems of composition and performance. Musical practice, on the
other hand, continued to do its own ÒtalkingÓ, and changed and progressed due
to the innovations of specific musicians or groups of musicians. While we
remember and perform the music which was influenced by Medieval and Renaissance
theory, and which is easiest to analyze and understand, some music doesnÕt seem
so clear, doesnÕt appear to fit, and appears odd. As Dorit Tanay says in ÒÕNos
faysoms contre Nature...:Õ Fourteenth-Century Sophismata and the Musical
Avant-GardeÓ, even as late as the
fourteenth-century, musical practices such as ars subtilior cannot be
explained particularly well with theory in the traditional sense, but rather
must be understood within the context of a larger cultural interest in logic,
philosophy, and numerology.
I
find this useful, because it shows that the zeitgeist cannot be
exhausted by any canon of explanatory papers. With this is mind, as well as the
evidence that musical aesthetic truths seem to be far from universal from time
to time, I wish to show how conceptions of musical meaning have changed more
specifically by unraveling musical formalism and classicism as it has evolved
into the early 20th century. Unfortunately, just as the understanding of the
Western canon evolved, the Western canon began to change. And here we can see
the discontinuity between the universalist expectations of critics and musical
praxis. Despite the many attempts to formulate and reformulate a critical
justification for the universality of the music of Mozart and Beethoven, each
attempt ultimately fails when we interrogate our knowledge in the context of
the critical discourse.
Formalism
and Autonomy
For
a long time, to be a connoisseur of music meant understanding the stylistic
conventions of a Beethoven symphony, and being able to ÒfollowÓ a work within
the tonal framework of Western harmony, like one keeps score at a baseball
game. One could marvel at the choices a composer made, because these choices
would seem novel or fantastic within the framework of the system, which would
seem to delimit creative possibilitiesÑmaking the great composers and works
standout from those that made the most obvious and clichŽd prototypes of, say,
the Sonata-Allegro form. This is the basis of the film Amadeus. Salieri was a
composer, but Mozart was the Composer. Of course, the world is always more complicated than the
presentation one receives in an introductory lecture, or a ÒhistoricalÓ film.
In this section, I wish to deconstruct a variety of understandings which are
bolstered by formalist criticism, and which reveal, in their reversal, a model
for a single contextual model for a broad-based discursive critical
understanding of music. In some senses, this is the easiest strategy to attack
musical understanding, since it is predicated on the 20th centuryÕs ongoing
questioning of conventions. However, I wish to show that even 20th century
adoptions of formalism are unfortunately shortsighted, because although they
arise from different social conditions than 19th century, they still wish to
make universal claims of a form of classicism or essentialism.
I will begin with
what I believe is a normative understanding of MozartÕs music, and the
questions it raises of a musical canon of knowledge. Then I will address two
historical formalists, one from the end of the 19th century and beginning of
the 20th, Heinrich Schenker, and one from the middle of the 20th, Theodor
Adorno. I believe that each formulation of formalism reveals a similar
weakness: swirling around practice, there is always a critical discourse in
music that paradoxically weakens the autonomy of music that formalists wish to
attribute to the objects of their criticism. In this sense, even formalism
concedes to elements of contextuality and reference in their criticism by
implicitly appealing to the structures of convention as stand-ins for the large
system and structure to which they are representative.
Case
Study: Mozart
This is a case
study of Mozart, the kind of picture one may receive if one read every
introduction to classical music book in a public library. It draws upon notions
revealed in works as disparate as Amadeus and the romantic critic Hoffmann.
Among the
individuals still revered, Wolfgang Amadeus Mozart stands as an almost
inescapable figure. More than simply a name in the long list of societyÕs
patriarchs, Mozart not only established several long-lasting stylistic precedents in
his treatment of the sonata form, but he is uniquely portrayed in todayÕs
culture as a musical geniusÑsomeone who understood music better than
any other. He conceived of music in a far more advanced and complex way than
most listeners could imagine, but understood fundamental tenets of musical
enjoyment so intuitively that he was able to create music that could be enjoyed
by all. And this Òintuitive understandingÓ still seems to hold true today, in
the culturally resonant melodic fragments that are recalled again and again,
remaining fresh even in the minds of todayÕs unrelentingly fashionable,
commodity-driven Òculture junkies.Ó A simple search in any Internet search
engine or on-line file-sharing application reveals that MozartÕs music will
continue to hold rewards for every age that has the tools to appreciate it.
The
stories of MozartÕs magnificent memory for music and ability to Òcompose in his headÓ certainly qualify
as extraordinary, and reveal the efforts of the historians to place Mozart as a
kind of high priest of music. In historical terms, of course, he was following
HaydnÕs lead, but at the same time it is hard to compare the two without
thinking of Mozart as the more transcendental composer. Whereas Haydn was a
great cultural barometer, and the first significant composer in the symphonic
tradition, when Mozart began to explore the language Haydn helped to create, it
seemed that Mozart was perhaps born to do so. He was able to perform magical
acts of historical progression and synthesis. He, for instance, empowered his
orchestral music with the same drama found in his operas, a drama deriving from
a true understanding of human emotionsÑcontrolling us by commanding our
innermost desires. He cut through the murky realms of the previous century,
which stretched from the spiky emotional dissonances of MonteverdiÕs
revolutionary opera to the abstract games of BachÕs private paper music,
consolidating aspects of both extremes, and presenting his compositions as
well-balanced essays on tonal hierarchy, in forms which represent the familiar
Western integration of logic and metaphysics (the rigorous, though na•ve,
evolution of thought to a new institutional paradigm of rationality).
Whether
or not the grand narratives about MozartÕs abilities are true, it can be
assumed that the mainstream of musical scholarship regarded him in this unique
light. He was a consummate musician able to tap into a different kind of
consciousness, prized and inaccessible by the general public. In this way he
was a mystic. But he worked with the self-determination and new concerns of an
Enlightenment thinker, using a system of structure that emulates the logical
progression of a philosophical argument and in the process, perhaps
metaphorically linked the rationality of the mind to an objective mechanistic
cosmology. These are the concerns of the critics, and Mozart passes with flying
colors.
The
Problem With Asking Too Many Questions
Asking
questions of this commentary-fueled picture reveals the goals of the canon, and
the problems that emerge when we attempt to distance ourselves from the
discourse. The autonomy of Classical music and the cultural peak it represents
are so fundamental to our understanding of the discourse of music that to deny
it as simply contextual makes one reconsider the notion of intrinsic meaning in
music. But this is exactly the kind of intellectual revolution required to understand
the importance, as well as the contingency of the discourse. Thus, we must not assume that simply
because a statement about music is ultimately bound to the critical discourse
(and thus by definition, ÒmerelyÓ linguistic) it has no bearing on an understanding
of music itself. Rather, these underlying concepts are what must not only
structure the discussion of music, but also create the context for our musical
enjoyment. They reinforce cultural norms, and thus, the creation of new
artworks as well as new criticisms. Just as a discussion of musical meaning is
impossible without a musical object, so is a discussion of the musical object
impossible without our intuitive understanding of the musicÕs meaning.
Conversely,
this does not mean that all of our conceptions of the music are necessarily
accurate simply because they are reinforced by the grand narratives of musical
meaning. The difficult and lofty enterprise of delimiting and demystifying the
class of musical objects means ÒviewingÓ these musical forms from a perceived
seat of objectivity (or at least keeping an open mind). If we accept an
essentially dual-substance theory of music (with an ambiguous/ÓunknowableÓ
meaning encircling an objectively viewable form), then we must ask what
constitutes the fundamental nature of any musical formÑwhat kind of ÒthingÓ the
musical object is, and then determine what, for instance, Classical music Òis.Ó
And this is where the difficulty comes. We are forced to make judgmental
decisions that will impact the rest of the discourseÑfor there is as much
confusion about the nature of the musical object as there is ambiguity of
musicÕs meaning.
Academic
scrutiny and understanding of the musical object usually utilizes a variety of
tools to present the ÒstoryÓ of a piece of music. Usually, we are presented
with a formal outline of some sort that is supposed to be, in the strictest
sense, what is going on in the music. But it is hard enough to figure out what
the music is. Obviously contextual sources aside, we are faced with the fact
that the music manifests itself in a variety of guises: in performances, in
recordings of performances, as copy written Òworks,Ó documented as notation,
and, perhaps, in the composerÕs head. Because music is possibly the most
difficult of the arts to isolate, it is difficult to know what factors
influence our understanding of music.
We
could call each of these forms of music, except perhaps the contents of the
composerÕs head, which would at least be understood as somehow causally related
to the music. Unfortunately, it is, of course, beyond the scope of any current
discipline to know how musical structures were manifest in, say, MozartÕs head,
and to determine if the music manifested itself in MozartÕs head differently
than in WagnerÕs head, or Leonard BernsteinÕs head. But no matter our view on
this topic, each opinion that could be said would reveal a limited notion of
musical essence. I do not wish to deny the possibility that music can be many
things simultaneously (ÒmereÓ sounds, natural mathematical relationships,
culturally influenced forms), but I also do not want to posit that the ultimate
nature of the musical object as we conceive it cannot be sorted out logically
simply because of its perceived multiplicity.
The
fact that music is translated through a variety of mediaÑfrom composer to score
to performance to listenerÑindicates that much of the composerÕs intent cannot
be shared by the listener. And yet, musical analysts have always relied on
every tool available to find out about the music. They listen, consult the
score, dissect it into sections, reduce it to components.
One
may simply attempt to Òspell outÓ what occurs in a piece, which amounts to a
description of oneÕs understanding of the pieceÕs stylistic context. This is often
described sequentially, although sometimes it is done in terms of Òstructural
importance.Ó One may perform such tasks on a variety of levels, hoping to show,
perhaps how the composer may have gone about the task of creating a piece.
Ultimately, however, every formal analysis is stunted by the fact that the
musical objectÕs perceived autonomy is a separate matter from the process of
creation or the linguistic labels given to stylistic conventions. Through the
critical discourse, which posits artistic masterworks, the musical object seems
to take on an inscrutable and radically unified wholeness. The deconstruction
of critics takes away the very qualities they wish to imbue the music with.
After all, no two analyses are the same. Additionally, it is impossible to know
the whole story of how a composer such as Mozart may have gone about composing
a piece of music.
Despite
all these problems which music presents us, we nevertheless come to critical
understandings thanks to critical discourse, which hides all of these problems
by positing unity where there is multiplicity, continuity where there is
discontinuity. Far from freeing us from the problems of delimiting the music
object, these critical understandings ultimately trap us in new and more
insidious conclusions. While the apparent goal of criticism is to streamline
understandings so we may all participate in the creation and appreciation of
music, it instead places tyrannical limits on the possibilities of what music
is and should be like. Considering the incredible variety of sounds and
arrangements of sounds found throughout musical history and from one subculture
to another, this side effect of critical ÒclarificationÓ is to destroy the
possibility of understanding music with any other models, while maintaining the
same kind of legitimacy in the critical discourse.
ExamplesÑSchenker
and Adorno
An
example of critical limitation in action is one of the great music theorists of
the 19th and early 20th centuriesÑHeinrich Schenker, a truly supreme formalist
in an age of formalists. He is the great example of an individual who valued an
understanding of the musical score as a prerequisite to understanding music
fullyÑtaking the musical Òconnoisseur'sÓ(musician and composerÕs) attitude as
the mean rather than a listenerÕs. Ultimately, he was responding to the
generally slippery notion of what is important in music, and attempted to pin
it down on all levelsÑcreating a formula to perfect the translation from score
to performance and critique, which he held as companions.
Schenker
believed that a composition could be reproduced correctly
only
if the performer had grasped the composerÕs intentions as revealed
by
the score, and if he had developed an aural sensitivity to the
hierarchy
of tonal values which it expressed.[6]
Schenker
believed that every tonal work (and tonal works were his only concern) relied
on a fundamentally hierarchal structure, which he generally described with
three major levels of structural significance, labeled the Òforeground,Ó the
Òmiddle ground,Ó and the Òbackground.Ó He believed this system would Òwork for
all structures, not just reductive analyses of sonata principles.Ó[7]
The foreground consisted of the sensuous medium of all surface notes, the
immediate experience of melody. The middle ground consisted of the larger scale
movements of tonality, and the background consisted of the tonal centers a
piece traverses, relying on the notion of the tonic triad as the fundamental
structure of tonal music.
An aesthetician, Schenker believed that
most laymen appreciate music only on the more sensuous, emotional level of the
foreground, and a deeper understanding of the music, required of all music
connoisseurs, comes with an intellectual understanding of the background and
middle ground as well. Indeed, according to Schenker, only with an
understanding of the background and middle ground does the foreground gain its
true significance, a fact that eludes many, but accurately describes the
workings of the piece within the tonal hierarchy. This distinction of levels of
musical understanding was described as the Òstruggle between coherence and
novelty.Ó ÒThe layman desires melody as a fulfillment of the moment,Ó he said,
Ò[but] melody can be seen as a broader horizontal realization of vertical
ideas.Ó[8]
SchenkerÕs
contribution to theory was his belief that each small element in a piece is
important only within the ÒcontextÓ of the whole piece.
ÒJust as Freud
opened the way for a deeper understanding of the human personality with his
discovery that the diverse patterns of overt behavior are controlled by certain
underlying factors, so Schenker opened the way for a deeper understanding of
musical structure with his discovery that the manifold of surface events in a
given composition is related in specific ways to a fundamental organization.Ó[9]
Of
course, this method only works with the most diatonic tonal music (Beethoven,
Brahms, et al). Canonical composers as diverse as Wagner and Stravinsky fail to
achieve ÒgeniusÓ status, due to their unique takes on structure. Schenker is,
of course, one of the many who give special status to the Classical style,
equating the conventions of the tonal system with the notion of musical
autonomy.
This
is unsurprising, for the style of most diatonic classical music can often be
reduced in Schenkerian analysis with few loose threads. However, SchenkerÕs
understanding of context, which aligned itself with notions of musical autonomy
on the one hand, and unraveling the ÒgeniusÓ composerÕs intent and methodology
on the other hand, seems blind to the underlying contextual factor which links
the two.
This
contextual factor is the style utilized in the creation of the musical object, a
style that is rarely fully autonomous. And it must be conceded that the more familiar
an audience is with a style, the more likely they are to enjoy it. The process
of translation decoded through any process of interrogation (in, say,
Schenkerian analysis) can only work in a world that already concedes
contingency to a shared method for addressing the musical object.
However,
the scientific reduction of a Schenkerian into foreground, middle ground, and
background relies on a specialized method for addressing the musical object
that is not shared by all those who appreciate Classical music, namely the
notion of structural levels, a ÒgeniusÓ method of composition which cannot be
taught, and a process of Òstructural listening,Ó which relies on an
acquaintance with the musical score.
At
this point, we can see how formal understandings of one kind of music can
disregard the contingency of the very stylistic elements that hold the music
together as an objectively viewable form. Of course, Schenkerian-style analyses
cannot purport to give all music an equal chance, only music in which the
Òtonic triadÓ holds a modicum of significance. What Schenker does reveal is how
commentary-fueled canons are created, and the kind of commentary that is needed
to justify a given canon above other works.
However,
the stylistic concerns of formalism are not the only critical prescriptions
that place one kind of music ÒaboveÓ another. As notions of 19th-century
ÒRomanticismÓ were questioned by the rationalizing force of modernism, the
stylistic autonomy of Mozart or Beethoven was seen by composers such as Schoenberg
and critics such as Adorno as radically abstract. And the institutional
commentary-fed validity of Òautonomous art musicÓ was reified and turned into a
normative aesthetics for music in modernity. Part of this reification of
autonomous art was the continued, explicit denial of any sense of FoucaultÕs
explanation of the repressive power of illusory Institutional values,
including, of course, the notion of music as discourse, or language. This
aspect of classicism, and musical autonomy is equally important for my
purposes, since Òsample-basedÓ music not only questions stylistic norms, it
blatantly refers, and is not autonomous. Therefore, a critique of modernist
formalism is needed.
In
ÒMusic and Language,Ó a broadly formalist treatise, modernist critic Theodor
Adorno outlines the problems of thinking about musical meaning in terms of
language, and yet, in his insistence on the closed formal system, and his
reification of abstraction, he neatly creates the possibility of just such a
conception. He says that music resembles a language, but is not a Òsemiotic
system.Ó The meaning of an English sentence can be understood if one knows
English syntax, the meanings of the individual words, which stand for things in
the real world, and the appropriate cultural associations they bring. Music is
often described in terms of language, with its phrases and sentences, but
musical ÒsentencesÓ do not stand for anything else.
Instead,
according to Adorno, there is an apparent ÒambiguityÓ of meaning, as we unwittingly
attempt to equate the ÒlanguageÓ of music to language. The traditional
formalist view, a thread that runs from Eduard Hanslick to the Pieter van den
Toorn, is that music resembles Òdance and architectureÓ[10]
more than literature in its total lack of external referent. Whereas the
ÒsubjectÓ can clearly be isolated in various portrayals of the same subject
matter in painting, literature, and drama, a purely musical setting does not
clearly reveal any specific subject existing apart from the notes themselves.
Thus, in music, there is no division between form and content, which are
identical, and to speak about meaning in music is to speak about the notes
themselves.
In
her discussion of Òstructural listening,[11]Ó
Rose Subotnik brings up that, in SchoenbergÕs case, the musical ÒideaÓ truly
supersedes style. She quotes from Style and Idea, Ò[the
responsible composer] will never start from a preconceived image of a style; he
will be ceaselessly occupied with doing justice to the idea. He is sure that,
everything done which the idea demands, the external appearance will be
adequate.Ó[12]
Though
SchoenbergÕs music, and its Òidea,Ó may appeal to the Schenkerian need for
autonomy (though it would not fall into foreground, middle ground, and
background), it is unlikely that his music is as easily understood or enjoyed
by the public. Can we thus concede, with Schenker, that the only true enjoyment
of music comes from structural listening? Or does it rather seem that most
music relies on a style, which presents itself in the foreground, translated
through a familiarity, and that music without a style is paradoxically less
likely to convey an idea?
Unsurprisingly,
Adorno holds up ÒautonomousÓ and abstract modernism such as Schoenberg, and
doesnÕt say much about art such as Futurism, Dadaism, and Surrealism, or the
musical Avant-Garde that surrounded him. If he were to have done so, he may
have discovered the way out of the major problem of Modern Art, the seemingly
irreversible division between high and low. What Adorno identifies as ÒartÓ is
actually only a splinter of the larger art culture. The mid-19th century
commodification of culture, which grew into the mass culture of the 20th
century is, for Adorno, the fundamental condition of the Modern. And the only
legitimate Modern art is that which rigorously challenges the commodity-status
of culture (specifically the move towards commodity as Òcommodity
through-and-throughÓ), and in its autonomy is still capable of expressing the
individual genius creator. What, then, of the ÒpopularÓ culture? Adorno doesnÕt
like it, even though it is the larger sphere of influence, and in HabermasÕs
terms, Òthe lifeworld.Ó
Andreas Huyssen, in After the Great
Divide, attempts to understand the circumstances of the Modern/mass culture that Adorno
is concerned with, and he quotes John BrenkmanÕs historical analysis of the
Modern.
The
European bourgeoisie, still fighting to secure its triumph over
aristocracy
and monarchy, suddenly faced the
counterrevolutionary
task of suppressing the workers and
preventing
them from openly articulating their interests.[13]
AdornoÕs
exemplar of the modern is Arnold Schoenberg, who never pandered for an
audience. What, then, of the ÒpopularÓ culture? As a commodified form of
culture, ÒpopularÓ music is seen as a Òthread bareÓ ready-to-wear cultural
product, which relies on a mindless audience and the control of an elite group
of lowbrow fashion mongers.
What
would it mean for culture to be a Òcommodity through and through?Ó This is a
claim, one would think, that Adorno should have to justify with a competent
critique of so-called commodity forms. Unfortunately, AdornoÕs brutal attack on
popular forms does not include formal critique. He sees the specter of fascism
in every pop hit, and is unwilling to make the jump toward actual analysis. It
is as if by virtue of his stamp of Òcommodity through and through,Ó popular
culture is by definition devoid of the possibility of genuine expression or
originality, and thus Adorno is unwilling to take the time to address specific
formal aspects of popular music. Instead, he relies on a few dogmatic
assertions based on his distrust of standardized forms, seeing the signs of
mass culture as a greater signifier for not only the imminent destruction of
earlier social and economic conditions, but ultimately for a world devoid of
art.
If
the concept of decay, which cultural philistines love to cite against
modern
art, is justified anywhere it is in popular music.
My
Fair Lady [is] a show that musically fails to meet even the most
primitive
standards of originality and inventiveness.
[The
hits] reckon with the immature, with those who cannot express
their
emotions and experiences, who either never had the power of
expression
or were crippled by cultural taboos.
[1]
Although
part of a larger program criticizing mass culture, his exploration of popular
music cannot extend past a few pages of biting attack.
Though
many have criticized AdornoÕs lack of attention to the specifics of popular
forms, I wonder whether this neglect is not simply a result of his Marxist
program, or whether he simply affirms the Modernist aesthetic that Òformal
autonomy=genuine expressionÓ using a Marxist basis to justify its claims. The
formal, academic art of Modern movements are, for Adorno, the last bastion of
genuine expression, because they rely on formal autonomy and a distanced
individual genius. But there is more to this division than standardization in
the Òsong hitÓ vs. the formal autonomy of integral serialism. SchoenbergÕs
cultural discourse is different from ÒHungarian schmaltz [and] Prussian
Puppchen brutality,[14]Ó
not only because of its ÒgeniusÓÑunderlying AdornoÕs Beethoven/genius worship,
there may simply be an elitist hatred for the mob.
There
are many examples in AdornoÕs own lifetime that call his basic premises into
question. Movements such as Dada and Surrealism, which also embraced Freudian
and Marxist critiques of Modern culture, were, however, significantly different
in that they attempted to unite art and lifeÑdistorting the distinction between
form and content, but not through abstraction. Rather, these artists were just
as likely to draw their material from the world of mass culture as academic
formal deconstruction. And commodification itself was turned back on itself as
social critique. In other words, Dada and Surrealism took discourse as read,
and created discourse about discourses, without a reliance on the autonomy of
art for artÕs sake. Artists such
as Man Ray and Bu–uel embraced the spectacle of the Parisian cinema, for
instance, and philosophized upon its psychological effect. And because they
knew the culture, they could manipulate its signs. They turned it back upon itself, recognizing the changes of
the Modern age, and thus, igniting a seemingly new way of making artÑnot
trapped in the Utopian formalism of the past, but allowing their art to take
the form of commodityÑnot AdornoÕs Òcommodity through and through,Ó but a
discursive statement that admits of the discontinuity in the apparent continuity.
The artwork reveals the individual artistÕs point of view within the context of
the discourse as illusion of continuity and autonomy.
Formalism,
it seems, is trapped by its own indefensible defenses of itself. Can we really
believe that the only good music is that which displays three hierachical
levels, or which is the least understandable? Is popular music bad in the
tautological ways Adorno wishes to present? The narratives of musical autonomy
are terribly contingent both in a formalist and a classicalist ideology because
they cannot hold over time, or explain the changes in practice over time.
With
this critique of formalism in mind, we may open our eyes wider and take in the
full musical universe as it truly appears. In the later part of the 20th
century, the definition of music, like that of art in general, has been
broadened. My analysis of this deconstruction is that musicians and composers
simply could not hold on to autonomous definitions of ÒmusicÓ after the
simultaneous impulses of populism and avant-gardism threatened the narrowly
balancing formalism of high modernism. These defenses of music, like the
formulation of a ÒMedievalÓ theoretical system, were written long after the
creation of the practices they praise, and only provide defenses of these
disintegrating practices.
Today, there is a
new aesthetic breakthrough begging to be understood. But it requires an
approach that does not discourage an understanding of the critical discourse,
and how it shapes our individual and societal appreciation of music. Rather,
this breakthrough can be seen as the larger application of SchoenbergÕs
emancipation of tonality to the discourse of music-itself.
The
obvious flash point of this breakthrough is John Cage, who claimed not to
distinguish between sounds, and also began the process of defacing the myth of
musical autonomy. I hold John CageÕs ideas very dear, because although he
worked within a particular stylistic milieu, he did a great deal to expand
general notions of what music can be. In a shimmering moment, he revealed the
artificiality of the institutional definition of music, as part of an
avant-garde program of deconstruction.
Although
Cage despised rock ÔnÕ roll, the Do It Yourself aesthetic of garage bands is
mirrored in the experimental nature of pieces such as Music of Changes or Indeterminacy. And in one of a
million historical overlaps, John Cale, a pianist who worked with Cage and
David Tudor (as well as the New York experimenter LaMonte Young) went on to
create The Velvet Underground, the premier American Garage Band, which adopted
stylistic elements from Cage and from YoungÕs more minimalistic, meandering
piano scores. 4Õ33Ó is certainly a personal statement in the medium of
sound, and did more than open the door to musical experimenters. Cage injected
the musical discourse with a freedom that stretched into the popular sphere and
would forever change music-itself.
But
since the 1960s, Andy Warhol, John Cage, and the Velvet Underground, there has
been another breakthrough in the musical discourse which is not as stressed as
the role of John CageÕs avant-garde deconstruction. This is the digital
revolution, which has lead to new methods of music making, and, I contend, a
further elaboration of the deconstruction of notions of institutional, or
ÒautonomousÓ music. Information about historical connections and influences
between pieces are more available than ever before. And the digitization of
music has made no fundamental class, or institutional distinction between high
and low music. They are sold in the same arena, and Philip Glass writes
symphonies based on David Bowie albums, just as ÒambientÓ New Age recordings of
John Cage pieces circulate on file-sharing networks. Works such as Plunderphonic, by John Oswald,
point the way to a new aesthetic of musical creation and reception, based on a
new understanding of music-as-discourse. There are a variety of different, but
similarly educated composer/performers, who value the novelty and above all the
plurality of sounds (that is to the larger field of musical discourse) and
their cultural referents (that is, to the even larger field of cultural
discourse). They consider no division between high and low, because
digitization has hidden the institutional signs of value (everything, for instance,
is a copy). At the same time, digitization, and the information revolution, has
allowed the traditionally slow process of meaning-apprehension to accelerate,
and the discourse to grow exponentially. The methods available to
de-and-reconstruct the musical material in works such as Plunderphonic reveal that,
indeed, practice may change our values, and values change our consciousness and
reception of art-in-general.
I believe we have entered a period in
which the wealth of discursive possibilities in the field of artistic creation
has overshadowed the institutional norms that have held fast into the era of
modernism, whether these norms be notions of musical autonomy through
Schenkerian or Adornoan formalism. Because of this, I believe our notions of
discourse must be expanded, as the information which contextualizes our notions
of musical meaning are provided in the form of a much larger and more open
framework. The Internet, for instance, allows individuals from different
cultures and socioeconomic levels to speak as equals. And the number of
opinions available is mind-blowing.
But
attempting to understand the discourse isnÕt enough. To do so would once again
whitewash the issue of real musical practice. I believe that contemporary music
reveals a world-view that more or less accepts basic ideas of subjectivity,
contingency, and relativism, as well as the subversion of commodity and
institutional values, as a theoretical starting point. In the next chapter, I
will describe this new music, and provide a rich context for understanding it.
CHAPTER
TWO: SAMPLES AND EXAMPLES
In
the last chapter, I addressed some of the problems of musical formalism, namely
its ultimate contingency and the unfair value it gives to some music over
others. This, remember, is due to
the privileged place that the canon of specific works attains through the
intermediary of the musical formalism. In this chapter, I will describe some of
the music that has interested me over the years, but which I feel inadequate to
critique, because the critical apparatus that would allow such a criticism is
simply not at my fingertips. This is music that the critical systems of musical
formalism ignore or look down upon, because it cannot be stylistically
reconciled with the canonical works or the criticsÕ formal systems.
I do not wish then, from this conclusion, to imply that formalist criticism
is the only form of musical criticism around. However, contextual criticism,
such as Susan McClaryÕs, which concedes historical contingency, appears to fall
into many of the same traps as the work of formalists. McClaryÕs work, in which
she deconstructs contextual meanings in a variety of musical forms, can
frequently seem inconsequential despite the myriad epiphanies which link
context to content, and trace the sometimes invisible strings of influence
through analysis.
For instance, when we learn that SchubertÕs homosexuality may be manifest
thematically in the Unfinished Symphony, or that the true history of the blues is that of the exploitation of
African culture, we may ask ourselves, ÒWhat bearing does this information have
on an immediate appreciation of the musical object?,Ó especially if we still
hold onto a semblance of artistic autonomy, and disinterested criticism.
For these reasons, I will attempt to simply present a variety of findings
in contemporary music as objectively as possible, without attempting to
highlight what contextual value they may have as the way to understand them. I shall leave my critique for the next chapter. For
now, I will simply present examples of music that I believe call out specifically for a new critical understanding. I will also present
quotations from commentators who take new critical approaches to contemporary
culture. It is my hope that these will provide possible clues for a critical
understanding of this music, or at least the paradigm shifts that seem to have
occurred over the last century.
The first striking discontinuity between a formalist story of music and the
music I have observed is that the ironclad division between high and low may
not be so solid. There are individuals who place themselves in positions that
may have formerly seemed controversial, but have now transcended the nominal
labels of the previously fixed institutional hierarchy. Of course, one must
perceive continuity if one is to perceive discontinuity, and I do not mean that
institutional praxis has been abolished by individual practice. This is
obviously not true. Instead, I merely wish to offer a few examples of a perceived
realignment of perceptions of continuity. Milton
Babbitt, for instance, is a composer who lived two musical lives, one in a
world of academic composers, atonality, and scientific precisionÑthe other as a
maven of Broadway and popular American song. These lives did not meet on the
level of practice, despite a passion for both. There was always ÒseriousÓ and
ÒpopularÓ music. Raymond Scott is an example of a composer from the time frame
(both figures were on the forefront of electronic music in the 1950s), but one
who may be seen as prefiguring a more contemporary musical pluralism. Raymond
Scott is the composer of The Toy Trumpet (CD track 1), Powerhouse, and other
famous tunes known mostly from arrangements by Carl StallingÑthe composer for
Warner Bros. cartoons. However, Scott also worked in the cutting-edge on
electronic music, composing works such as Soothing Sounds for Babies. This work cannot simply be pigeonholed into ÒseriousÓ or ÒpopularÓ music
categories. It is a three-hour-long stretch of soft electronic ambiance, which
clearly anticipated works like Brian EnoÕs later ÒambientÓ works like Music
for Airports. It is unclear what audiences at
the time thought they were buying when they purchased the album in the 1960s,
with its smiling Gerber-like baby photo on the cover of its three volumes.
Clearly, this was an experiment in both composition and marketing. This was not music that had been heard beforeÑit certainly did
not fall into the conventions of the ÒpopÓ music of the time. And this work,
which utilized experimental stylistic forms, and electronic instrumentation,
but was sincerely marketed for the public, is not the only example of ScottÕs
inventiveness and embracing of the signs of both popular and serious music.
Scott would compose advertising jingles for toy companies and IBM, create
electronic versions of his popular ÒnoveltyÓ jazz compositions, and combine
this Òvulgar materialismÓ with an experimental spirit just as independent and
uncompromising as Charles Ives or Harry Partch. Just as neglected by the mainstream public as Milton Babbitt, Scott
used his obscurity to create a personal world of sounds that responded to
modern culture and music. Taking a cue from the tape composers Pierre Henry and
Pierre Schaffer, who first spliced music, sound effects, and ambient noises
together to create a new listening experience called musique concrete, Scott created works such as DonÕt Beat Your Wife Every Night (CD track 2), which splices de-contextualized advertisements and electronic
splashes, to create a work of art that accepts the full range of expressive
possibilities given by the culture. Scott composed music for cartoons, but they
were extremely difficult to play. He made advertising jingles, but they
utilized tape manipulation and synthesizers he created in a studio he dubbed
ÒManhattan Research Inc.Ó With pieces such as LimboÑTheOrganized Mind (CD track 3), he and Jim Henson (later of Kermit the Frog fame) recycled
material from an IBM advertisement, and created a short narrative psychodrama about
a man who can file each of his memories perfectly in his file cabinet-like
mind. The situation quickly turns to disaster when his bad memories become
misfiled. Utilizing sound effects and jarring electronic noise, this narrative
is about as far from the ÒhappyÓ jingle as possible. And these two pieces
present the two halves of the work done at Manhattan Research Inc. DonÕt Beat Your Wife Every Night and LimboÑThe Organized Mind reveal that Scott found a way to make even the most vulgar commercial form,
the commercial advertisement, into a potent form of personal expression. These
hybridized pieces, while only one form of expression available to the
contemporary composer, nevertheless provide the seed of a new music that was to
emerge out of musique concrete. Like the
painting after photography, and the novel after film, music after the tape
contains new expressive possibilities. And these possibilities specifically
point the way toward an acceptance of discontinuity. The splice is the new
element, and grows from its humble beginnings to infiltrate all forms of music.
Does this facilitate a Ònew way of hearing?Ó And if so, what is the larger
context for this change? I wish to present two long quotes about changes in
technology that brought about the current paradigm of information perception. I
will then show how these examples relate specifically to understanding music
that utilizes these technological changes. The first is from Jonathan Sterne,
talking about the emergence of telephony, and the emphasis it placed on the ear
for the purposes of sound and sound reproduction. The second is from Paul D.
Miller (DJ Spooky, that Subliminal Kid), and relates to the use of the ÒcutÓ in
all post-cinematic media.
Jonathan Sterne on the emergence of telephony:
Prior analyses of sound had been more oriented toward a particular SourceÑtheories
of sound took the voice and the mouth, or music and a
particular instrument (such as the violin), as ideal-typical for the analysis,
description, and modeling of sonic phenomena. The mouths and
instruments were taken as general cases for understanding sound. Sound-reproduction
technologies informed by this perspective attempted to
synthesize sound by modeling human sonic activities like speech or musical
performance. In contrast, the new sciences of sound would in a sense
(or, rather, in the sense of hearing) invert the general and the specific
theories of sound. No longer themselves general categories of sound
fit for theory construction, the mouth, the voice, music, and musical
instruments would become
specific contenders for audition in a whole world of
sonic phenomena. In this new regime, hearing was understood and modeled as
operating uniformly on sounds, regardlessof their source. Sound itself, irrespective of its source,
became the general category or object for acoustics and the study of hearing.[15]
DJ Spooky on the emergence of the ÒcutÓ:
ItÕs been a while since the autumn day in 1896 when George Melies was
filming a late afternoon Paris crowd caught in the ebb and flow of the cityÕs
traffic. One of those random occurrences that always seem to be at the core of history then took place. Melies was
in the process of filming an omnibus as it came out of a tunnel, and his camera
jammed. He tried for several moments to get it going again, but with no luck.
After a couple of minutes he got it working again, and the cameraÕs lens caught
a hearse going by. It was an accident that went unnoticed until he got home. When the film was developed and projected
it seemed as if the bus morphed into
a funeral hearse and back to its original form again. In the space of
what used to be called actualitesÑreal contexts reconfigured into stories that the audiences could relate to
- a simple opening and closing of a lens had placed the viewer in several
places and times simultaneously. In the space of one random error, Melies
created what we know of today as the ÒcutÓ - words, images, sounds flowing out
the lens projection would deliver, like James Joyce used to say Òsounds like a
river.Ó Flow, rupture, and fragmentation - all seamlessly bound to the viewerÕs
perspectival architecture of film and sound, all utterly malleable - in the
blink of an eye space and time as the pre-industrial culture had known it came
to an end.[16]
I take these quotes to be enlightening possible answers to the questions
ÒDoes [the splice] facilitate a Ònew way of hearing?Ó And if so, what has
caused this change? I also think these quotes address the original question
brought about with the Raymond Scott exampleÑthat is, does this Ònew way of
hearingÓ necessarily privilege a kind of musical pluralism over a hierarchy of
musics? The first quote is from Jonathan SterneÕs The Audible Past (2003), a book which attempts to explain the cultural origins and
implications of sound reproduction, beginning with Alexander Graham BellÕs
earliest experiments with the ear phonautograph (a machine that used an actual
human ear as a conductive membrane!). Through the course of his research, which
spanned the creation of the numerous early sound recording devices and their
mass-cultural reception, Sterne came to the realization that a fundamental
change in thinking about sound was required to
create the modern world of telephony and phonography. Sounds had to become equal
and emancipated, as the focus
was changed from designing sound reproduction to model diverse sources of
sound, to focusing on their universal endpointÑthe human ear. In other words,
the differences between sounds were not what created the sounds: for the
purposes of sound reproduction, the practical difference between the sound of a violin and a trumpet, a jungle and a crowded street was not the
difference between a violin and a trumpet, a
jungle and a crowded streetÑbut rather, only their distinctive imprints on the
recording media. From this, it
seems to follow that a cultural norm of music predicated on the power of
recording can easily delimit the once slippery notion of the essential nature
of any music. When we focus on the ear, rather than, say, a score, or the
contents of a composerÕs head, we can easily point to the record as the source
of the music. And unlike a Schenkerian analysis, any understanding of this music must be heard. However, as a record, this music also retains its
objectivity. Every time it is played, it will sound the same. There are many other aesthetic
conclusions to be drawn from this discovery and the subsequent paradigm shift
Sterne describes. Because all sonic transducers are modeled after our own ears,
our ears can be ÒfooledÓ by recording media into believing that, say, the
violin is being played in the middle of a crowded street even if the two were
simply played on two Gramophones at once. The auditory experience is similar to
the experience of collage, or any context in which the ÒartificeÓ of art seems
to be glaringly transcendental.
Unlike the music of the 19th century, which could certainly be
programmatic, in examples ranging from the timbre of the English horn in
BeethovenÕs Sixth Symphony (Pastoral) and MahlerÕs use of the fiedel in the Fourth Symphony to create a sense of Òthe demonic,Ó or Òthe
country,Ó to the wind-machine in StraussÕ Alpine Symphony, the new expressive potential of recorded sound would not be relegated to
the realm of Òspecial effectÓÑclearly separate and secondary to the more
important sonic material, the tonal music played by the live orchestra.
I cannot help but see the advent of recording and the experiments of
composers like Charles Ives snugly fitting into the new sonic paradigm
together, as if to justify this historical hypothesis. In IvesÕs purely
orchestral music, there is a sense in which a true sound-collage is being used,
utilizing orchestration and poly-tonality to mimic sounds are they truly heard.
When Ives has two different melodies playing against each other, in say, Three
Places in New England, it truly sounds
like two bands converging. And this experience can be seen in two different
lights. First, it can simply be heard as programmatic. However, in its
composing Òfor the ear,Ó it seems more than simply programmatic. He does more than simply evoke an air of pastoralism, he
actually has a brass-band play a brass-band tune. Through this transformation,
we can see a freedom that reveals the seed of musical pluralism. Because IvesÕs
musical decisions are focused on a specific sonic outcomeÑthe choice of his
material can be anything that provokes this outcome. And the experience of this
music functions just as much on the Òmusical surface,Ó as in the deep structure
of formal construction. As music becomes more mimetic in its possibilities, the
imaginary structures of construction, brought about by the need for fixed,
abstract conventions which Òfill-inÓ for emotional states, are no longer our
only refuge Of course, music is
still the most abstract of the arts, and I do not mean to suggest otherwise.
However, music, which exists in the medium of sound need not simply be the auditory expression of paper music, once the
surface textures of sound are allowed to vary in complexity as well. What music
is ÒaboutÓ seems to be the full range of composing for the ear.
It is with this physical evidence that John Cage seems justified in his
call for the equality for all sounds. But the story does not end here. For, at
the beginning of the 20th century, there was another new context with which to
understand sound. The experience of two brass bands converging may be highly
mimetic, but this is simply a maturation of the possibilities already available
in 19th century orchestral music. The experience of listening to a gramophone
playing jungle sounds while another gramophone plays, say, Caruso singing La
Donna Ž MobilŽ is strikingly
different in kind from mere
quotation or program. And this is where Miller is most useful.
Paul D. MillerÕs Rhythm Science (2004) is a sprawling and enlightening series of essays about the attempt
to understand contemporary culture. In the essay ÒRhythmic Cinema,Ó Miller, a
prolific electronic composer and conceptual artist, attempts to equate the
emergence of musique concrete, and the
influence of the ÒcutÓ in music to the discovery of the first film Òcut.Ó
Although Miller does not specifically show the links in practice between the
early film cuts and our perceptions of modern music, his book, as a holistic,
freewheeling path through his personal reflections on the contemporary world
makes one consider the integral, but invisible, impact of technology upon our
everyday conceptions and perceptions of the world.
In MillerÕs essay, the ÒcutÓ of musique concrete is the same ÒcutÓ of a DJ who combines the foreground, middle-ground, and
backgrounds of a dance track, or an ambient soundscape sourced from
field-recordings. The ÒcutÓ is also synonymous with the most violent
juxtaposition in Surrealist and Dada montage. The ÒartisticÓ experience
fostered by the traditional avant-garde in formulations such as BretonÕs
Òobjective chanceÓ can only come about through the process of confusing life
and art. For this reason, in music, the sounds of our everyday subjective experiences must be perceived objectively
through the natural combinatory power of the mind. In Òthe Surrealist Situation
of the ObjectÓ (1935), AndrŽ Breton described the Surrealist experience of
Òobjective chance,Ó ÒThat sort of chance that shows a man, in a way that is still
very mysterious, a necessity that escapes him, even though he experiences it as
a vital neccessity.Ó[17] Surrealist works attempt to replicate and provoke this experience,
sparking memories of the unconscious by depicting a seeming melding of
conscious and unconscious modes. Works that include the juxtaposition, or the
violent cut, in BrŽtonÕs formulation, provoke active interpretation of the
world rather than passive acceptance. This
new objectivity of chance leads us to new possibilities of artistic expression,
and ultimately to the power of sample-based music, which I feel is the most
tangible expression of technology utilizing the impulses of the avant-garde and
Òpost-Warhol populismÓ to create a music that grapples with sounds and signs of
our time. If Mozart represents the values of the Enlightenment, then I find
that sample-based music represents the artistic possibilities and values of the
consumer age.
Before I go on to finally reveal Òsample-basedÓ music, I will quickly
recap, so as to make its emergence all the more revelatory. It seems that
avant-garde attitudes derived from Dada and Surrealism have provided a new way
for artists and composers to respond to the changes in technology, as well as
institutional notions of beauty. The possibilities of musique-concrete, latent in such referential forms as programmatic music, achieves a new, purely
sonic character as the sounds-themselves gain prominence in
the age of recording. Because the sounds-themselves are full of referential
possibilities, which link music to other music and to other sounds, and because
contemporary technology has the ability to reproduce these sounds perfectly
from ear to ear, composers can exploit sounds and the power they have upon by
presenting them to us in the context of a new form of pure music. Unlike the pure music of the past, which rejected
sound in favor of relationships between abstract tonal systems, this pure music
is concerned with the connections sounds have in our mind, as they form a kind
of gestalt sonic simulacra. In IvesÕs music, this may be the sum-total of the
familiar tunes he presents us with, and their intersection with the conventions
of 19th century tonality. In ScottÕs music, this may be the
intersection between the simple and complex, the experimental and the
established. Therefore, the effect of this music, which has the ability to fool
the ear, and plunder from popular culture, has qualities similar to Pop Art and
SurrealismÕs objective chance. This is due to
the recontextualization of the ordinary into the artistic, and vice versa,
which provokes new contexts for understanding both the nature of art and of our
commodity forms. From these roots,
we come to Plunderphonics, and John Oswald. Oswald, who emerged as a
compositional figure in the 1970s, comes from the polyglot world of
post-phonographic musical practice; he is a composer and an improviser, and he
straddles the worlds referred to as jazz, pop, minimalism, and musique concrete. He has composed orchestral
works, ballets, string quartets (one of which was commissioned by Kronos), and
he has worked in rockÕnÕroll and jazz improvisation. However, he began with musique
concrete and this is probably what he is
best known for. After
experimenting with many techniques and styles in the early 1970s, he chose to
focus on one that he dubbed ÒPlunderphonics,Ó culminating in the release of Plunderphonics
album in 1989. This then became his preoccupation for
the next eight years, and he enjoyed fame and massive underground cult status.
Although the word Plunderphonics means only Òstolen sounds,Ó John OswaldÕs
Plunderphonics are more than simply an excuse to plagiarize, as most music
inevitably does, or to re-release other peopleÕs material under his own name,
like the work of Audrey Flack. In these works, Oswald systematically dismantled
commercial recordings and used the material as fodder for brand-new
compositions which inevitably act as both a commentary on the original material
and a brand new composition, which may use preexisting sounds and conventions,
but takes these elements and places them in a variety of new compositional
contexts. Although OswaldÕs Plunderphonics project may have begun at a time
when his products would certainly be deemed illegal if released commercially,
the project was complicated as other forms of ÒplunderphonicsÓ became a main
source of Popular music. One may
ask at this point what the difference is between Plunderphonics and the works
of contemporary composers like Luciano Berio, George Crumb, and others who
compose music that obviously references other music. To this, I reply that the
differences between Plunderphonics and Sinfonia, for instance, are significant. Plunderphonics is done purely in the
medium of the sound-itself. There is no score, and there are no musicians to interpret.
In Plunderphonics, the sounds themselves are copied identically. Most
importantly, Plunderphonics cannot be analyzed in the way that Sinfonia can. One can go bar by bar and never
forget that Sinfonia was composed by a composer for the concert hallÑit is not a pure commodity
product, and it does not emulate or directly dialogue with the pop music of
dance halls.
After all, sample-based pop hits, the direct result of live shows in which
DJs mixed and matched different rhythms, melodies, textures, and timbres from
records, grew in popularity with the emergence of hip-hop in the 1980s. And hit
songs began to emerge in which the musical backing for rappers was directly
ÒsampledÓ from preexisting commercial recordings. By the mid-80Õs, the DJ
became a superstar, finding more and more exotic and esoteric material to use
in new tracks. Hits like Run-D.M.C.Õs ÒWalk this Way,Ó (CD track 4) a cover of
the Aerosmith song that used the actual music from the Aerosmith record, and
the Beastie BoyÕs Licensed to Ill album (CD track 5), which used splashes of Led Zeppelin and AC/DC gave
Oswald a new, and unexpected audience. Oswald responded to this phenomenon by
marketing his Plunderphonics project as a call-to-arms to allow sample-based
music, with its myriad possibilities of expression, and the relative
availability of sampling technology, the same kind of legitimacy as so-called
original popular music. After all, Plunderphonics was something brand newÑa
chance to create a new kind of music that uses our new technology and does not
subjugate it to the old. And thus,
Oswald saw Plunderphonics as more than just an artistic statement.
Experimenting with sample-based music himself, and seeing the explosion of
interest in sample-based music all over the world in even the poorest
communities, Oswald saw the sociopolitical impact of this affordable, homespun
consumer form. People were interested in making music with this new technology,
and as a free-jazz improviser, among other things, Oswald saw the potential for
a new musical explosion.During World War II concurrent with Cage's
reestablishing the percussive status of the piano, Trinidadians were
discovering that discarded oil barrels could be cheap, available alternatives
to their traditional percussion instruments which were, because of the socially
invigorating potential, banned.
The steel drum eventually became a national asset. Meanwhile, back in the States, for
perhaps similar reasons, scratch and dub have, in the Eighties, percolated
through the black American ghettos.
Within an environmentally imposed, limited repertoire of possessions a
portable disco may have a folk music potential exceeding that of the
guitar. Pawned and ripped-off
electronics are usually not accompanied by user's guides with consumer warnings
such as "this blaster is a passive reproducer". Any performance potential found in an
appliance is often exploited. A
record can be played like an electronic washboard. Radio and disco jockeys layer the sounds of several
recordings simultaneously. The sound of music conveyed with a new authority
over the airwaves is dubbed, embellished and manipulated in kind.[18]
Amid all this hip-hop and social advocacy, Oswald also released his own
sample-based music to the musical community. His auditory cut-up of a preacher
and Led Zeppelin appeared as an insert in the Canadian magazine Musicworks (CD track 6). In a 1994 interview with Brian Duguid, Oswald described how
he came to create more and more Plunderphonics pieces during this period,
including using the BeatlesÕ Revolution in a ballet. The definition I'd set up for plunderphonic was music that
was recognizable in some way, and the transformation of that music. I think the
most successful examples use music that is the most recognizable. It's more
delightful to me to have these pop figures, and by pop I also include
Beethoven, as the working materials. There are things that work as plunderphonics for me, I've got a tape based on
Edgard Varese's Poeme Electronique , and had the same sort of
experience of having changed round something that's very familiar to me, and
there are examples on plunderphonic of stuff like that: Anton Webern,
and Ligeti, and Cecil Taylor, and Captain Beefheart. But the ones that were
most interesting to me were things like Bing Crosby, where you'd play it for
somebody who had no great knowledge of all sorts of other things that were
happening in the twentieth century outside of the pop mainstream, they'd have
some sort of reaction based on that thing that's recognizable within it. The thing
that's very nice in a way is that I think there is a bridge between things that
are often ghettoized as being extreme twentieth-century avant garde techniques
and pop music. The two things can coexist.[19]
Oswald released the Plunderphonics album, containing pieces that deconstructed the Beatles, Michael Jackson,
Anton Webern, and others, to radio stations in 1989. As Oswald predicted, the
pieces that got the most notice were the ones that used the most familiar
sources. His liner notes include:
Track 7 Ð ÒPretenderÓ Ð Over the course of this song Dolly Parton gets an aural
sex change.
Track 4 Ð ÒWhiteÓÑ Bing Crosby sounds a little pink on our version of the
best-selling single of all time.
Track 24 Ð ÒRainbowÓ Ð Judy Garland's
theme is played in a dozen harmonic layers. Eventually only the slow, low ones
are left.[20]
But
what does one make of
this music? After discarding formalism, and presenting theories, possibilities,
and quotations, I will attempt, with this rich context in mind, to present my
own notes about a single Plunderphonics piece. However, it isnÕt easy to come to any definite
conclusions. This is one of the problems of formal deconstruction. And for this
reason, IÕm simply attempting to describe the music before I analyze it per
se.
Brown
(CD track 7) is 3Õ56.Ó This may be the length of a standard pop song, as are many of the
pieces on Plunderphonic, though its
structure is not perhaps what one would expect from a standard pop song. Like
much musique concrete, there are more
Òquick changesÓ going on then can be discerned initially, so that the
experience of the music continually changes as one listens to it several times.
A series of distinct musical moments can be discerned, each utilizing a
different combination of musical materials and style of recombination. Most
basically, I identify the sounds of the hip-hop group Public Enemy, James
Brown, and a bop saxophone as the main sources of the music. The Public Enemy
track seems to be from It Takes a Nation of Millions to Hold Us Back (CD track 8), their landmark second album, which is noteworthy for
containing sound-effects, as well as beats, among their samples. The liner
notes identify the saxophonist as Charlie Parker, and a shooting gun sound
effect as ÒMatt DillonÕsÓ, from the opening of the TV show Gunsmoke. Brown is typical of
pieces on the Plunderphonic album, because it
is a dense, and highly original composition, but itÕs meaning, if it has one,
is unclear. There are many possible connections to be found between OswaldÕs
source of material, but like the examples of Ives, Scott, and even Berio, it is
unclear how to think of these connections without appealing to earlier formal
models. While we may have a laugh at the oddness of it, and it certainly seems
from OswaldÕs comments this is intended, there seems to be something more going
on here with the sounds-themselves. The
piece, though titled Brown, is attributed
to Public Enemy, not James Brown. In this release, Oswald attributes each track
to only one of the many artists he uses. And at first, this label seems
appropriate. The first few seconds of the piece are dominated by Public EnemyÕs
distinctive ÒBomb SquadÓ production style. Still new at the time of Brown, Public EnemyÕs beats were themselves plundered from a variety of sources,
and they utilized a heavily condensed, sound-effect driven mix which sounds
somewhat similar in some aspects to the music of Italian Futurists like Russolo[21]. Police sirens and high-pitched squeals, along with the sometimes
smooth/sometimes hiccupping contours of Òscratching,Ó in their original
context, evoked the lack of stability and threat of danger always hovering
above the lives of inner city blacks of southern California. Like the loud and
violent raps, the fast and precarious juxtapositions of the music seemed to be
filled with an emotional restlessness.
Oswald skips through this easily identifiable material quickly in the first
seconds of the piece. He has heavily edited material from a variety of sources
to create an intense and sudden burst of beats and sound effects, but quickly
it is interrupted by different, but also identifiable sounds. There is the
noisy Charlie Parker, and an especially forceful James Brown, who is always
stammering, stuttering, screeching, and squealing at his highest ability.
After each of these elements is introduced, the three engage in an
energetic and disconnected dance that swirls through the stereo range. Beats
bounce, horns blast a single phrase looped quickly and pitch-shifted up. Brown
is clipped in grunts and moans. A loop forms from the variety of sources, and
its tempo modulates like a vamp. As the loop is trimmed, the rhythm briefly
emphasizes the offbeat and there is a jazzy rhythmic complexity.
For a moment, the ensemble crystallizes into a heavy free funk ensemble,
until the samples begin to diverge again.
Out of this chaos, a JBÕs horn blast emerges like a ray of light. For the
next two minutes, the Godfather of Soul brings out an assortment of his
Ògreatest hitsÓÑin the form of horn blasts and screams. In a conscious
metamorphosis, the initial high-pitched squeal which features prominently in
Public EnemyÕs It Takes a Nation of Millions has been replaced by a new squeal manufactured from James BrownÕs
high-pitched screams. Gun sound effects shoot out a rhythm.
Is Oswald playfully replacing Public Enemy with a new simulacra of
pop-culture violence, or simply presenting us with a history of ÒbrownÓ music?
Like most Plunderphonics music, the Òprogram,Ó if there is one, is unclear.
What seems clear, however, is that OswaldÕs music could not do what it does without using samples, and the impact that they have on us as
distinctive and recognizable sounds. In his
interview with Brian Duguid, Oswald describes this phenomenon.
Any time I wanted a particular sound for something and realized that the
particular sound was something that already existed in somebody else's piece of
music, I thought, well, if this is the best example of it, I could do something
else, but what I'm really just doing is paraphrasing or making a facsimile. I
shouldn't compromise, I should just stick the best thing in there. I would make
a piece for a choreographer, and as an example for rehearsal, take that
guitar-chord thing from the beginning of The Beatles' ÒRevolutionÓ and do an infinite loop of it. I had the intention of replacing that with
another guitar player. I brought Henry Kaiser into the studio, and we'd sit
around trying to imitate the timbral quality of that guitar, it was easy to get
the rhythmic feel of it. We got a facsimile of it, and it was pretty good and
it had its own little interesting characteristics, but in the end I liked the
other one better. I might have liked it better, the John Lennon version,
because it had precedence, things are in a sense your roots, that you've heard
for a long time, they're difficult to supersede. Cover versions of popular
songs are very perverse things. So I would keep the John Lennon thing, and then
I'd think, well, it seems like the sort of thing you could get in trouble for
doing, well John Lennon got killed, and I was in no position to ask him for his
permission. And the people I knew were working for him, imagine trying to call
them up and trying to get permission for
a no-money project? So, I was doing all this stuff but I didn't have any sense
of it being easily available to other people.[22]
As one might expect, the primary response to Plunderphonic has been to praise OswaldÕs deconstruction of familiar pop-culture
signifiers. He is seen in the context of the long line of ÒPop Artists,Ó such
as Andy Warhol, David Salle, Matthew Barney, Douglas Coupland, and others who
are burdened by the label Òpostmodern.ÓPopular on-line music magazine Pitchforkmedia had this to say of PlunderphonicÕs recent reissue:While parts of 69 Plunderphonics
96 are immensely fun
to listen to, other parts are just as much fun to analyze. "Btls,"
the first track on the retrospective, begins with the resonating final chord of
the Beatles' "A Day in the Life," a beautifully blasphemous way to open
up an album that pays little heed to any kind of musical convention. As if that
weren't enough, the opening chord of "A Hard Day's Night" is then
layered directly over that famous final chord of "A Day in the Life,"
resulting in a chord that sounds like utter dissonance, but makes perfect sense
from a logistical standpoint. This is the musical equivalent of painting big
flirty eyelashes on a picture of Jesus Christ. And it rocks.[23] IÕm not quite sure why ÒBtls,Ó (CD track 10) is
the Òmusical equivalent of painting big flirty eyelashes on a picture of Jesus
Christ,Ó considering the understated nature of this trackÑone of the more
creative re-contextualizations that isnÕt necessarily burdened by overt
quotation (after all, only single chords are used). But this reveals the difficulty
of separating the cultural associations we have from the sounds-themselves. And
this may be a complication to understanding sample-based music. Meanwhile, when
musicologists like Chris Cutler attempt to give Plunderphonic the true artistic autonomy and ÒauthorshipÓ that the
original tracks possess, he seems to be making the case in a legalistic manner. So
I hear John Oswald's version of Dolly Parton's version of The Great Pretender,
effectively a recording of Oswald playing
Parton's single once through,
transformed via varispeed media (first a high speed cassette duplicator,
then an infinitely variable speed turntable, finally a hand- controlled
reel-to-reel tape - all edited seamlessly together). Apart from the
economy of this single procedure of controlled deceleration, which is, as
it were, played by Oswald, no modifications have been made to the original
recording. However, although the source is plainly fixed and given,
the choice, treatment and reading of this source are all highly conscious
products of Oswald's own intention and skill. So much so indeed
that it is easy to argue that the piece, although 'only' Parton's record,
undoubtedly forms, in Oswald's version, a self-standing composition
with its own structure and logic - both of which are profoundly
different from those of the original. Oswald's Pretender would still
work for a listener who had never heard the Parton version, and in a way
the Parton version never could. Though the Parton version is, of course,
given - along with and against the
plundered version. What Oswald
has created - created because the result of his work is something startlingly
new - is a powerful, aesthetic, significant, polysemic but highly focused
- and enjoyable - sound artefact; both a source of direct listening pleasure
and (for our purposes) a persuasive case for the validity and eloquence
of its means. [24]
At the beginning of the chapter, I attempted to raise some questions about
the validity of an exhaustive attempt to isolate Òcontextual meaning.Ó It is
difficult to say what Plunderphonic is about precisely because the question of its contextual meaning seems to
be what it is about. On the one
hand, we have OswaldÕs powerful sociopolitical statements about the importance
of sample-based music, which, in an almost Marxist-context is seen to restore
agency to a disenfranchised part of the population. We then have his reasoning
behind using samples in his own compositions: because the sounds he wishes to
use are best found in prerecorded material. Both of these reasons for
sample-based music skirt the most obvious outcome of this kind of music,
however. What is to be done about the fact that the cultural associations we
have for these samples infringe upon our understanding of the artistÕs
intention? Why does he use these samples in this way, rather than other samples
in another way?
Oswald, has, himself, complicated this issue by denying an explicit program
or politics in the music itself, but at the same time, courting the outrage of
a copyright-bound music industry by, for instance, making the cover of Plunderphonic a nude womanÕs body with Michael JacksonÕs face. It is easy for a hip
pop-culture media outlet like Pitchforkmedia to see Oswald as a musical Jeff KoonsÑanother misunderstood artist whose
use of appropriation has branded him a kind of outlaw art-kid.
On the other hand, artists and critics like Cutler attempt to stress the
opposite view, selling Oswald as an extremely personal artist. Cutler says that
one need not have heard Dolly PartonÕs original in order to appreciate Pretender
(CD track 11). This seems to me to be taking Oswald
too seriously in the other directionÑfrom heteronomy to autonomy.
Synthesizing these views, and taking into account OswaldÕs full body of
work in the field of Plunderphonics, I would say that this extreme example of sample-based music is the music which must be explained if we are to form any ÒaestheticsÓ of
sample-based music, which is fast becoming the norm in popular music. Over the
last few years, artists like Jay-Z, who utilizes esoteric samples as the basis
of his rap music, have become the darlings of both critics and consumers.
Sample-obsessed rap producers like RZA now do film music to movies like Ghost
Dog (1999), directed by Jim
Jarmusch and Kill Bill (2003-2004),
directed by Quentin Tarantino. With the Plunderphonics project, people began to
take serious notice of the implications of sample-based music, and Oswald
himself has answered back by continually advancing and obscuring the ÒmeaningÓ
of his project.
I argue that, following from the preconceived notions of music we have,
these confusions arise from trying to fit Plunderphonics into our notions of
what music is, or should be. Although formalism like SchenkerÕs, or AdornoÕs is
not in vogue, there is a normative sense of where different cultural products
fit in the hierarchy of institutional imperative. For now, RZA and Jay-Z can be
explained as mutations of the normative consumer entertainment form known as
ÒpopÓ music. But, as pop becomes the more advanced technological and expressive
medium, it cannot simply be discarded as a kind of vulgar materialism with no
real value or meaning. We must think about music differentlyÑnot simply in
terms of ÒhighÓ and Òlow,Ó or ÒautonomousÓ and Òheteronymous.Ó The
institutionally-constructed value that we place on aesthetic objects, and their
discursive role in the realm of imagination and cultural critique may begin to
change more dramatically as the technology of the digital age begins to
structure our thoughts and memories in a new 21st century paradigm. Like DJ
SpookyÕs Òcut,Ó and SterneÕs explanation of telephony, perhaps the advent of
this new highly referential and obscure music, which takes sounds and their
associations in a rich stew, will turn out to be the newest paradigm shift. When Plunderphonics was initially released to radio stations in 1989, Michael Jackson had all
copies burned for copyright reasons, although he himself plundered BeethovenÕs
9th Symphony at the beginning of his HIStory album. Was this a double-standard, or merely an unclear time, in which the
connection between what Jackson was doing and Oswald was doing was unclear?
There has been a historic change since then. Plunderphonic was re-released commercially in the year 2000, and it has yet to be pulled
off the market, despite being the most explicit appropriation of a variety of
pop musicÕs sacred cows yet created. For these reasons, it is essential that we
come to some understanding of plunderphonics, and other sample-based music. I
hope to do so in the next chapter by returning to Foucault, and providing a
model that concedes to the discontinuities of discourse in such way as the
splice renders necessary.
CHAPTER
THREE: MUSIC AS DISCOURSE; PLUNDERPHONICS AND FORMALISM
I
hope that the last chapter made clear that Plunderphonics dwells among a
complicated jungle of cultural referents and critical responses. And although I
assert that sample-based music has the ability to affect an audience in new and
unique ways, I cannot say how or why this may be until the facts of its reception are understood in a clearer light. It is easy to provide
quotes from a variety of media sources, but I will now synthesize these views
and attempt to create a formal architectonic within which we may objectively
judge them. If this seems like a regress to a formalist paradigm, I argue this
is necessary for any critical pursuit that attempts to understand and
categorize a societyÕs artistic output. Otherwise, description and analysis
ultimately become something else. I read Conventional Wisdom by Susan McClary and the works of Greil Marcus
[1], as personalized narratives of musicÕs
many social roles. But this kind
of endeavor is distinct from a clear explanation of music that can guide a
listener to music appreciation. For this reason, I want to keep the positive
aspects of traditional formalism (namely, its systematic thought and its
objectivity) and dull its negative aspects (its frequent chauvinism, for
instance) without resorting to a purely subjective form of criticism or simply
a deconstruction of earlier formalist dogma.
At
the heart of this matter is a simple question: How, amid our myriad
understandings and responses, can music like Plunderphonics be described? While
this is a general problem for music as a whole, it is all the more perplexing
for Plunderphonics, which appears at first to emerge without clear stylistic antecedents.
In
Deconstructive Variations, Rose Subotnik
addresses the importance of sifting through Òpurely formalistÓ understandings
of music until they reveal other descriptive
elements hidden in the cracks. Her best example, is Schoenberg and Adorno[25], who both rely on technical understandings of music, but let their dogmatic understandings of formalism
color this ÒscientificÓ pursuit. And, analyzing Adorno, or SchoenbergÕs
analyses, we should separate the curds of
critical dogma from the whey of technical analysis. After all, their
understanding of formalism is distinct from
the formal structures in their musical works. And yet, we sometimes need their
explanations to understand what would theoretically be clearly perceptible in formal music. If we follow SubotnikÕs model, we can see a way to
categorize these curds and whey separately, revealing a sort of Òextra-musicalÓ
description hidden within formalist descriptions.
These ÒhiddenÓ descriptions expand the possibilities of Òmusical
descriptionÓ such as the categories that Peter Kivy presents in The Corded
Shell (technical, emotive, biographical, and autobiographical), and function
on the level of meta-critique, as well as the
description of the music. We can see Subotnik dividing the heady mess of KivyÕs
so-called technical description, and showing how it is often, in practice, colored with biographical and autobiographical elements. Is it enough to
say that together, all these
elements would make up a formal understanding of SchoenbergÕs music? For when we talk about SchoenbergÕs
music, it is difficult to separate these elements due to SchoenbergÕs ingrained
formalist ideology, which privileges notions of Òart for artÕs sake.Ó More
intuitively, but also less easily clear, Subotnik seems to appeal to the usual
sense of the Òextra-musicalÓ(i.e. the whole set of information we glean that is not covered by the purely technical) as another essential key in the understanding of music. Keep in mind that
this does not simply refer to that large category of KivyÕs: the emotive. And I take this experience to
include not just some purely scientific account of musical structure, added to
or contrasted with emotion and contextual knowledge. Rather, our experience of music cannot be delimited or understood outside of our continual
approach toward the art object as the object of a multi-faceted discourse. Problems of descriptionÑparadoxes, if you likeÑemerge most perniciously,
it seems to me, when we attempt to clearly define our ÒpureÓ experience into simple and discrete forms.
Using SubotnikÕs deconstruction of the kinds of formalism I addressed in
Chapter One, I feel that deconstuction of musical discourse becomes the next phase in my endeavor. I feel that Subotnik would tend to
agree that the art object should be understood as the object of a rich discourse, although she does not necessarily
tell us the limits of this discourse or how it functions. I wish to present two
quotes that provide the two goals of a musical description that expands to
include discourse. The first quote is her division of structure and styleÑa telling point,
because although it collapses the timeless quality of even KivyÕs endeavor
(although, to be fair, his subject of ÒmusicÓ is clearly aimed at a canon only
slightly larger than AdornoÕs), it still carries with the clear signs of
description needed to understand the conventions of musical objects, and their
historical emergence. Both
SchoenbergÕs work and that of Adorno provide massive evidence of
the degree to which the communication of ideas depends on concrete cultural
knowledge, and on the power of signs to convey a richly concrete open-endedness
of meaning through a variety of cultural relationships. Their
work supports the thesis that style is not extrinsic to structure but rather
defines the conditions for actual structural possibilities, and that structure
is perceived as a function of style more than its foundation. Even in
a crude sense I would argue that if we are forced in musical analysis to grab
hold of one end or the other of the dialectic between a style and a structure
that are always affecting each other, it makes most sense to define
the composerÕs starting point as his or her entrance into a preexisting
musical style.[26]
We Òdefine the composerÕs starting point as his or her entrance into a
preexisting musical style.Ó This statement alone posits the idea of style as a clear cultural idea, which I understand as a conventional touchstone
of musical practice. In an ongoing and changing practice, style also changes.
How? Since composers enter the discourse and depart from it, leaving their
variations and combinations of style in response to previous ideas, these touchstones
must belong to a heavily delimited discourse.
It is also clear that in our rich understanding of musical history, the
full realm of the Òpurely musicalÓ and the Òextra-musicalÓ is just as important
as their stylistic or structural components. And this second quote provides a
context for thinking about the discourse-itself, and the individual expressive and interpretative minds that change
cultural ideas through their individual discursive statements. Such a
[stylistic] emphasis does require a
constant effort to recognize and interpret relationships between the elements
of a musical configuration and the history, conventions, technology, social
conditions, characteristic patterns, responses, and values of the various
cultures involved in that music. And such an effort almost invariably requires
a willingness to recognize at least the possibility of some positive value in
the kinds of immediate, though often diffuse and fragmented, sense that sound
and style have for nearly all musical listeners.[27]
Creating a diagram for discourse
It is easier to apply
deconstructions of musical discourse and musical style to the works of the
past. We see styles and their antecedents. We can see how one work emerges from
others. For this reason, in traditional music, I have tended to favor
historically contextual analyses over purely formalist ones, because the axioms
of formal analysis tend to rely on standard compositional responses to standard
formal structures. Contextual analysis can help enrich a notion of how a piece
addresses these structures, but also can ask questions that reach outside of
these "purely musical" borders. For instance, when attempting to
understand the importance of Beethoven's symphonies, we cannot take their
history for granted. The Seventh Symphony can be described thoroughly,
key-change by key-change, and the significance of its composition need not be
faced. Luckily, however, the things that make Beethoven's 7th great for a
Schenkerian are the same things that make it great for a contextualist. One
could say "Beethoven shows how drama can be understood through the subtle
beauty of tonal connections." Or, one could say that Beethoven merely
makes good compositional choices through an understanding of the tonal
systemÑunderlying the piece is simplicity and balance. Whether the Symphony is
painting or a chess game, the tonal system gives a common denominator to
address a variety of descriptions. Perhaps this is due to the state of the
heavily delimited discourse of the 19th centuryÑand the fact that ideas of
structure and ideas of style tended to influence one another in an almost
teleological paradigm, as Subotnik has shown in her discussion of Adorno and
Schoenberg.
On the other hand, a Plunderphonic piece may lead us to a variety of
questions, such as "Can we understand the meaning of a Plunderphonic piece
in a way similar to our understanding of traditional music?," and
"What specific additional meanings can we glean?" Additionally,
"Is there a way to objectively judge them?" In this last case, the
advantages of a traditional formal analysis, colored by cultural ideas of
structure and style, would seem to come in handy. Or, in KivyÕs terms, we could
make an autobiographical description. We could simply go back to the
"Plunderphonics" essay by John Oswald and search for answers to these
questions. But while this method would aid contextual analysis, in itself it
would not contain the potential answers that Plunderphonic music holds, an
essential step if Plunderphonics is to have the level of aesthetic confidence
in the face of divergent discourses that previous musical forms have long-past
achieved.
Taking SubotnikÕs description of earlier music into consideration, I wish
to put forth a possible way of describing how Plunderphonics and subsequent
pieces might begin to be understood stylistically, as well as in the richer
contexts of a heavily-delimited discourse. Hopefully, this analysis will unpack some of the importance
of Plunderphonics by putting these pieces into some sort of historical
perspective.[28]
I have said a lot about discourse, and it is here that I shall finally make
the plunge and talk about music-as-discourse. This is not easily done, and
requires numerous distinctions to be made. I do not mean that music is the same
as talking, or writing. I do not even mean that music must, as its primary goal, seek to Òsay something.Ó What is clear, however, is
that any piece of music that can be defined as distinct from another, whether
composed or improvised, must be thought of as music. There is nothing fixed about
music outside of time or space. There is no Platonic sense of music. I take
music simply to be a socially-constructed form of art in the medium of sound.
However, in order to understand sound as music and not simply as noise or Òsounds,Ó something about the music must be
intelligibly musical about it.
Remember that Foucault has defined a discourse as a series of discursive
statements belonging to a single mode of formation, which have a semblance of
continuity despite their ultimate discontinuities. For the purposes of talking
about music-as-discourse, we must simply label this Òsingle mode of formationÓ music. And for each traditional, ÒlinguisticÓ discursive statement, we may
substitute a musical work. In a practical sense, musical works are
"discursive statements" because they are intended to be encountered
as intention.
Our semblance of continuity is the sense that one piece emerges
historically from others. The ultimate discontinuity is that each musical work
is ultimately only ÒitselfÓÑand can easily be identified as such.
I will distinguish music discourse, or talk about music, including music-critical discourse, or the talk of music critics and
commentators such as Adorno or Subotnik from music-as-discourse. In addition,
music-as-discourse must be defined so as to distinguish the musical objects
Adorno addresses from the musical objects Subotnik addresses. I label the intended
sonic manipulations of a piece Òthe
discourse of sonic pattern.Ó This is the discourse by which we can hope to
answer the question, "How do we describe this piece of music," in the
purest sense. This is the sense in which so-called Òextra-musicalÓ
understandings are traditionally discountedÑthe technical for Kivy. Note that the discourse of sonic pattern is not Òthe discourse of
sonic formÓ or Òthe discourse of sonic logic.Ó As Subotnik has pointed out,
these understandings of music, though they are often conflated, belong to the
realm of extra-musical as well as, say, KivyÕs emotive descriptions. They are contingent, inter-subjective, and not understandable
as clearly discrete historical steps. When a critic such as Adorno posits logic
or structure in the discourse of sonic pattern, he is positing (in the music-critical discourse) just this: that the discourse of
sonic pattern contains notions of structure and logic intrinsically. Therefore
this full category of the Òextra-musical,Ó a misnomer because it makes up the
bulk of our musical understanding, including KivyÕs other three descriptions,
and the meta-critical, are needed as well, just as in traditional music. In
traditional music, emotion is thought to reside in music, as well as mimesis,
and other elements of cultural-connectedness. Adding these aspects to the
discourse of sonic pattern adds a secondary series of possible answers to the
question of musical meaning, especially to the question, "What additional
meanings can we glean?" I wish to call this hybrid with the discourse of
sonic pattern Òthe discourse of sonic possibility,Ó for it encompasses the
whole possible object of musical description. While the discourse of sonic
pattern is more closely identified with Adorno, the discourse of sonic
possibility is SubotnikÕs fuller understanding of music-as-discourse. With the distinction within music-as-discourse
between the discourse of sonic pattern and the discourse of sonic possibility,
a few divisions in Subotnik begin to become clear. A Subotnik inspired,
Òextra-musicalÓ discourse helps to get at the root of the historical problem of
pitting any system of description against formalism by collapsing formalism.
Formalism sets itself up as "above and beyond" the constraints of
history, but in fact, it is merely a paradigm beholden to a historically
particular critical discourse that purports to
transparently unpack the discourse of sonic pattern. In fact, musical
ÒformalismÓ is merely a meta-critique of music-critical discourse, espousing
certain views of beauty over others, and not even getting to the real matters-of-fact underlying the discourse of sonic patternÑthe full-range
of historical conditions which allowed the 19th century symphony to emerge in
the first placeÑas a stylistic evolution from earlier conventions of sonic
patterns.
I hope to describe Plunderphonic and other pieces in such a way as to
explain the possible roles of the discourse of sonic possibility, without
making the same mistake of confusing the artistic object with the musical
discourse which shields it as Òcommentary.Ó I show how Plunderphonics pieces themselves utilize the
discourse of sonic possibility in such a way as to create a drastic change in
the means by which the music-critical discourse can cement a clear musical
formalism.
A Historical Split in the Discourse of Sonic Possibility
In music, as it has emerged, the discourse of sonic possibility has tried
to reduce itself into the discourse of sonic pattern. This is because, in
music, the most readily-available sonic content of any music (as understood
through artistic conventions) is the manipulation of pattern and certain basic
ideas of pattern. This may initially lead one to believe that the history of
music is simply that of a well-defined discourse of pure sonic pattern, and
nothing else. However, the discourse of sonic pattern, as it has emerged, can
also be understood as the history of larger systems of artistic abstraction
that belong more properly to a larger discourse of sonic possibilities. The
discourse of sonic pattern, as it has been envisioned by many canonical
composers and commentators, is, after all, only one possibility. Through the historical process of canon formation, the discourse of sonic
pattern has emerged as the only possible discourse for critics such as Schenker.
However, music cannot be purely understood as a pure discourse of sonic pattern
once it is conceded that the specific conventions we equate with these sonic
patterns are only understood in specific contexts of reception. Together, these
points lead us to the importance of reference, which is pivotal to
understanding music-as-discourse. Because
music can be understood as a discourse of sonic pattern, and also as a referent
to other cultural expressions, the history of music can be understood as a
story of parallel discourses. For instance, when Susan McClary describes
emergence of Baroque instrumental music from notions of drama displayed in
early Italian opera and oratorios, we can see a split between the discourse of
sonic possibility and the musical discourse that eventually led to the
emergence of "pure music"Ñwhat was once referential and contextual
quickly because logical and autonomous due to formal revisionism. In ÒTurtles
All the Way Down,Ó the first chapter of Conventional Wisdom, McClary argues that the cadential forms (including the evergreen V-I
cadence) emerge from specific solutions to setting text in operas through the
creation of the aria [1].
Although there is no longer the specific
dramatic content in the symphony that is understood to be in the opera, in the
form of either arias or recitatives, this sonic material carries with it the
pattern of the earlier system, which in its turn is an abstraction of previous
conventions of dramaturgy. However, in order to delimit these abstractions, commentary
and reference to any available source (usually through the conventions of
style) are needed to create an intelligible piece. Therefore, in music we have
the competing impulses of contingency and autonomy. The autonomy of music comes
about from its apparent lack of reference, once that reference has been freed
of its original context. The contingency is music's reliance on the initial
reference to come to its historical position, and its subsequent need for
convention to appear "musical" at all.
I
therefore posit an irreducible UR-discourse, which gave the Òpurely musicalÓ
elements of music (the qualities of tonality, for instance) their distinctive
character. At this stage, the sonic outcome of an initial
"extra-musical" concept and this extra-musical element were not seen
as competing, as in the case of the Baroque composer coming up with a way to
express emotion with a cadential structure. If a sonic element were meant to
function mimetically, it would not pose a problem to the autonomy of music. The
discourse of sonic pattern then emerged to manipulate the once extra-musical
concepts (such as the V-I cadence) as they became solidified as the rules of
abstract music. This discourse is still more distinct from the music-critical
discourse, which examines the whole enterprise with language, and makes value
judgments. But it is the mystery of the split into these two halves that makes
the discourse of sonic possibility so tempting. Although music may seem
autonomous and purely logical and analytic, it actually relies on myriad
contingencies. If we understood this, I believe we could make more honest music
that is not beholden to false dogmas. This possible future I entitle
"music's imminent self-awareness."
By this, I mean the destruction of the mystery of music, which is only
fostered by the critical agent. For there can be no mystery in unaffected prime
matter of music, which as John Cage has displayed, is the lowest common
denominator of sound. The formalist critic attempts to shield the contingency
of the discourse of sonic pattern by asserting in the critical discourse the
special properties of the "purely musicalÓÑwhich turned out to be the
"purely critical," or truly extra-musical; for sonic patterns exist
outside of the realm of good or bad. However,
the music-critical discourse and this kind of Òblind formalismÓ are at a
significant disadvantage. While they enrich an understanding and appreciation
of music as they would like us to understand it (and in the discourse, this is
equivalent to creating a canon and shielding it with sufficient commentary), it
cannot explain or promote the
culturally-necessitated advancement of musical practice. The effective critic
can only observe musical practice, and then posit in the music-critical
discourse the existence of a fixed form of the discourse of sonic pattern that
is inevitably at odds with the full scope of musical practice. Of course, this
is not the only possible role of the critic, or those that play the role of
both critic and artist. For instance, critics may come out in support of new
practices, of avant-garde notions and ideas.
But the avant-garde has historically found itself stuck in the rigorously
defined, critical atmospheres, in which commentary far outweighs the
work-itself. The Futurists wrote more manifestos than anything else.
SurrealismÕs founder, AndrŽ Breton, was likewise too busy explaining Surrealism
most of the time to actually create anything surreal. Avant-garde sensibilities
inevitably self-destruct when they are faced with these canonical expectations
and fall into the realm of traditional reception. What remains from these
movements should show us how practice actually proceeds: not through movements,
but the impact of the art upon individuals that make up the institutions, and
the stylistic changes brought
about in future works.
Music
has done well in its mystery and abstractness, and shielded itself altogether
from the avant-garde (with some notable exceptions, such as John Cage, Fluxus,
some free improvisation, etc.) But musical practice has also begun to free itself from the stifling atmospheres in
which critique outweighs sonic antecedents. Many examples of musical culture
indicate that music has rendered avant-garde ideas productive rather than
destructive. For instance, Brian Eno, a British pop musician in the 1970s,
influenced by minimalistic rock groups such as the Velvet Underground, and by
such pop-embracing artists as Andy Warhol, rediscovers and reformulates Erik
SatieÕs ambient music via John Cage, leading to new precedents in studio
production, as, for instance, displayed in the trilogy of albums Eno produced
for David Bowie between 1977 and 1979. Later, Philip Glass, in his own style of
minimalism composes symphonies for orchestra based on these albums. Then,
electronic music pioneer Aphex Twin creates a new sample-based piece of musique
concrete that combines BowieÕs voice with
the Glass symphonies (CD track 12). There are hundreds of similar examples.
And with Aphex Twin, we return to John CageÕs Òall sounds are equally
valid,Ó in the context of sample-based music, which takes the discourse of
sonic possibility as a more expansive and less-rigidly defined element of music
with which to compose a new piece in the discourse of sonic patternÑstill
existing, less fixed to one pattern or another thanks to the allowance for
previously Òextra-musicalÓ elements to gain superiority. Returning to my
critique of Adorno in the first chapter, and his notion of the commodification
of music ultimately challenging the musical autonomy he wishes to grant
Beethoven or Schoenberg: I say emphatically yes. This ÒautonomyÓ is revealed to
be the worst kind of illusion: one that limits the possibilities of art, and
the agency of individuals that do not buy into the self-ingratiating world of Modern
composer, in which we must study and scrutinize the life and the work of one
man for ages in order to arrive at the true potential of Òart.Ó This may get us
toward something, but it will never be clear what, outside of the particular
answers ÒplantedÓ in the music like some game of hide-and-seek. Entertaining
this may be, enlightening even. But this cannot be the only goal of art. After
all, intentionality, and primacy of structure may seem at one point to be the apotheosis of the artistic endeavor, but the
discourse of sonic possibilities reveals a multitude of additional meanings are
always there as well. Luckily, Schoenberg has survived. But it is because the
culture market has begun to find his strange sounds are saleable in a world
where difference and eclecticism matter. This kind of historical turn-around,
in which a figure reviled by critics can spurn a huge discography and active
performance, reveals that the music-critical discourse does not monolithically
determine the popular reception of a composerÕs music any more than the
commodity of ÒpopularizationÓ is monolithic in its establishment of
indistinguishable plastic products. Together, the popularity of Schoenberg in
musicianÕs circles and the growth of niche markets have allowed the democratic
institution of commercialization to keep SchoenbergÕs music afloat.
Again, to counter Adorno: this is due to the freedom of the musical
commodity market. Why the ÒfreedomÓ of Òcommodity?Ó Because commodity is
ultimately free from music-critical chains. The reality of the musical world,
in which VareseÕs records may well be used to test record players[29], is the
ÒconsumerÓ world in which we encounter sounds and their
patterns in a variety of contexts. Commodities find their audiences not out
among the infinite, in Platonic forms, but rather in the every-day world of
cultural reception. Adorno couldnÕt have imagined that popular music would
challenge our presuppositions of what music could be. However, the commodity of
music is a ÒpopularÓ phenomenon, which swallows up the divisions between high
and low. The
technology of recording, which changes music for both DJ Spooky and Jonathan
Sterne, also creates the real condition Cage describes, by creating the
lowest-common denominator of sound as an identifiable element. Therefore, the
object of our artistic deliberations is no longer the music-critical discourse
itself, displayed in a discourse of sonic pattern, but rather the discourse of
sonic possibilities, in which the commodified music functions on at least two
simultaneous levels. First, it exists as
pure sound for the first time. Sounds act as instruments, and are valued for
their timbral qualities. They can be manipulated in any way we like through
digital manipulation. The structures by which they are recombined by a piece
reveals something other than a pure form. This is because at the same time that
this commodified music sounds, it also references. The Plunderphone is a subtle, but powerful reminder of
this fact.
Yes, it is clear that I am countering the earlier status quo, and that my
zeal for the music I love may blind my objective lens. However, I doubt that
even Adorno could claim that musical commodities today are a monolithic
category of undifferentiated tissue. The claim that the true expression of the
individual is being replaced by some simulation of Ògenuine emotionÓ is harder
to dispel. But the burden of proof would seem to be on the traditionalist.
After all, who is not affected by the time that they live? And the variety of
products that emerge in the discourse of sonic possibilities are so strikingly
individualistic and diverse, I find any argument for the homogeneity of
emotions to be unjustifiable. Once again, John Oswald is my primary example for
the sample-based composer, but there are literally thousands of good examples.
A search of archive.org, the open-source media library (which allows donations
from anyone) reveals a virtual smorgasbord of discursive statements in the
discourse of sonic possibilities.
Plunderphonics and Music-as-discourse
John Oswald can thus be
understood as belonging to a new world of music discourse and
music-as-discourse, in which the object of his Plunderphonics is not simply the discourse of sonic pattern, or the music-critical
discourse, but rather, the discourse of sonic possibility, fostered by the dual
nature of the plunderphone. The reason Oswald is hard to define and describe
with traditional labels is because he doesnÕt really belong to any of them.
Rather, the sounds and references to practices that he uses are brought into
the new context of the Plunderphonics piece, which responds to all of the
associations we have through the discourse of sonic possibility in a new discourse of sonic pattern-the discourse of sample-based music. Perhaps this is why Oswald chose to focus on
Plunderphonics, rather than cementing himself into the pre-established
discourses of jazz or ÒseriousÓ music. The freedom he sought could only be
found in a new branch of
discourse. And the emergence of similar uses of samples could only have made
this choice seem all the more topical and exciting.
We can look at OswaldÕs music in this biographical and autobiographical
manner easily, since he talks about the importance of popular music forms
often. However, we donÕt need to, since the equivalent to a ÒtechnicalÓ
description of Plunderphonics would be meaningless unless it referenced the
sources Oswald clearly references. This is why I questioned Chris CutlerÕs
statement that a Plunderphonics piece, such as Pretender could be enjoyed if one had never before heard the original Dolly Parton
version. While his statement may be true, we should not fall back upon the
critical practice of subjugating context to musical autonomy. Clearly, this
music refersÑand not just through some mimetic technique. It refers because it is. Now, it is unclear why it refers, but this reference is important. Perhaps it provides a model for the discourse itself. When I speak of
musicÕs imminent self-awareness, this is the conclusion I tend to come to.
I concede to formalist views in that I believe music may be about music, if it is to be music and not simply sounds. Biographical and
autobiographical descriptions must be merely supplementary. I believe I can
come to some conclusions about Plunderphonics simply by understanding it as
music and music-as-discourseÑas sounds and as sounds in connection.
Plunderphonics must mean something because it references something specific, and because it does not diverge from institutional
notions of music so much as to seem like noise or just sounds. It clearly belongs to the discourse of sonic pattern. However,
the Plunderphonics album is an entry
in the discourse of sonic pattern that admits to the discourse of sonic
possibility. It may even function as an element of an UR-discourse for a future
sample-based music, which will gain its own sonic patterns. It is clear
however, that for the moment, that, in referencing the whole sphere of musical
commodityÑthat is, including Anton Webern, Cab Calloway, the Beatles, and the
rest, it admits that the sonic atmosphere we now dwell in is made up of more than sonic patterns. It is made up of actual, recorded sounds as well. And
this fact, which seems so obvious, has been downplayed by many composers who
place sonic pattern above everything else. These sounds, which are technically
the property of others, are also, like the patterns of Classical music, the
shared communal property of those whose musical world is based on them.
Therefore, not only what counts as music is
delimited institutionally, but so are sounds themselves. Plunderphonics creates new connections with old materials.
Therefore it rehabilitates the discourse of sonic pattern by rehabilitating the
agency by which the creation of new patterns can come to be an artform. For Oswald,
this is achieved through ÒPlundering,Ó or stealing. Stealing becomes the method
by which sounds can regain the importance that has been lost through the
music-critical discourse, but which has remained essential to those outside of
the system who still love music intellectually and emotionally. Sounds regain
this importance by rehabilitating the discourse of sonic pattern as the discourse of sonic possibility. This is the possibility of sounds
creating an intuitive connection by virtue of the individual, subjective, and contingent disjunction of the individualÕs
preference.
In the music-critical discourse, it is admitted that, through the discourse
of sonic pattern, one style influences another. In the musical discourse after
the discourse of sonic possibility is admitted, it must be seen that specific
sounds in certain combinations can be said to
influence future combinations of sounds. It is in this manner, I believe, that
we can evaluate and understand Plunderphonics. It is an open-ended activity that utilizes the most public appearances of
musicÑthat is, their sounds, in order to
promote the creation of new sounds through recombination. The patterns which
emerge are patterns which emphasize the discourse of musical possibilityÑthat
is, they are divergent, but are bound to fall into stylistic patterns. Plunderphonics utilizes the full palette of structureÑthrough-composition (Pretender), architectonic composition (such larger works as Grayfolded and Plexure), using each to
highlight the sounds being used and the possibilities of their patterns, as
well as their sounds as elements of the larger realm of the musical discourse
and the discourse of sonic possibilities.
Although
much formalism is predicated on the discourse of sonic pattern, a view of
musical meaning should also include the discourse of sonic possibility,
especially as musical works begin to innovate stylistically and make explicit
their connections to the conventions of recorded, commodified music. When
attempting to explain such contemporary works as the hip-hop collage or even
the post-musique concrete variety of sample-based music, it is important to take
a stance that does not reduce these works to the status of humorous side-note
to the ÒrealÓ music of the culture. I have not provided concrete methods for
analyzing Plunderphonics and its kin, but I have presented a possible model for
understanding and analyzing these works that presents them in the long line
of convention-challenging popular art forms from Surrealism to Pop Art.
Surrealism and Pop Art are important to the discourse of art because they have
changed our understanding of what art can be. Likewise,
Plunderphonics, in the same way that telephony changed our understanding of
sound, and the first cinematic cut changed our understanding of traditional
narrative, has the power to enlarge the scope of musical criticism and
understanding. When we take a more inclusive view of the set of musical
objects, we will see we are not limited by specific stylistic limits or formalist
designations which privilege any understanding over another (whether this
understanding be predicated on harmony or genre theory), but rather part of the
larger discourse which includes all sonic possibilities. My next goal will be
to provide a model for a possible critical analysis of works such as
Plunderphonics, but that is the task of another work. For now, the universalist
and the post-modern can both hope to coexist. The universalist knows that the
issue of musical universals is only really a matter of
viewing history in its entirety. Although the specifics of our music may
change, the nature of music-itself does not change if it is viewed
fundamentally as a discourse in the manipulation of sound. Likewise, the
post-modernist can be assured that in the future, the music that arises from
our inter-subjectively determined conventions will surely be open to the
limitless possibilities of the human mind. And because music could sound like
anything we could possibly hear, it is an entirely contingent and historically
determined endeavor. I hope that the format of this thesis has made apparent
that the subjective connections between diverse elements of the culture can
come together to form the new foundations for future understandings. In the case of music-as-discourse, to
discover the futureÉwe need only to listen.
EC
APPENDIX: MUSICAL EXAMPLES
Track 1 Raymond
Scott ÐÒThe Toy TrumpetÓ 2:59
From
Reckless Nights and Turkish Twilights
Released
October 27, 1992
Originally Released in 1939
Sony
Music Entertainment Inc. #65672
Track 2 Raymond
Scott Ð ÒDonÕt Beat Your Wife Every Night!Ó 1:44
From
Manhattan Research, Inc.
Released
May 16, 2000
Basta
Records #9078
Track 3 Raymond
Scott Ð ÒLimbo- The Organized MindÓ 4:33
From
Manhattan Research, Inc.
Released
May 16, 2000
Basta
Records #9078
Track 4 Run
D.M.C.ÑÒWalk This WayÓ 5:09
From
Raising Hell
Originally Released in 1986
Arista
Records #16408
Track 5 Beastie
BoysÑÒRhyminÕ and StealinÓ 4:08
From
Licensed to Ill
Originally Released in 1986
Def
Jam #27351
Track 6 PlunderphonicsÑÒPowerÓ 3:46
From
69 Plunderphonics 96
Released May 29, 2001
Originally
Released in 1994
Seeland
Records #515
Track 7 PlunderphonicsÑÒBrownÓ 3:56
From
69 Plunderphonics 96
Released May 29, 2001
Originally
ÒReleasedÓ in 1988
Seeland
Records #515
Track 8 Public
EnemyÑÒRebel Without a PauseÓ 5:02
From
It Takes a Nations of Millions to Hold Us Back
Originally
Released April, 1988
Def
Jam #27358
Track 9 Luigi
RussoloÑÒRisveglio di una Citta (1914)Ó 3:58
From
Futurism & Dada Reviewed
Released 1988
LTM Publishing #2301
Track 10 PlunderphonicsÑÒbtlsÓ
:56
From
69 Plunderphonics 96
Released May 29, 2001
Originally
ÒReleasedÓ in 1988
Seeland
Records #515
Track 11 PlunderphonicsÑÒPretenderÓ
3:34
From
69 Plunderphonics 96
Released May 29, 2001
Originally
ÒReleasedÓ in 1988
Seeland
Records #515
Track 12 Aphex
TwinÑÒHeroes [Aphex Twin Remix]Ó 5:18
From
26 Mixes for Cash
Released March 25, 2003
Warp
Records
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Adorno,
Theodor W. ÒMusic, Language, and Composition.Ó Translated by Susan
Gillespie.
The Musical Quaterly
77, no. 3 (Autumn, 1993): 663-672.
Adorno,
Theodor W. Introduction to the Sociology of Music. Translated by E.B. Ashton.
New York: Seabury Press, 1976.
Aristotle.
Politics. Translated
by Benjamin Jowett.
http://classic.mit.edu/Aristotle/politics.html
(accessed May 4, 2005)
Barkin,
Elaine and Martin Brody. ÒMilton Babbitt.Ó Grove Music Online, ed. L. Macy,
http://www.grovemusic.com
(accessed May 4, 2005)
Brenkman,
John. ÒMass Media From Collective Experience to the Culture of
Privatization.Ó Social Text 1 (Winter 1979): 94-109.
Breton,
Andre. Manifestoes of Surrealism.
Translated by Richard Seaver and Helen R.
Lane. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan
Press, 1969.
Burkholder,
J. Peter. ÒCharles
Ives.Ó Grove Music Online,
ed. L. Macy,
http://www.grovemusic.com (accessed May
4, 2005)
Cotter,
Jim. ÒFrank Zappa (1940-1993).Ó Music of the Twentieth-Century Avant-Garde:
a
Biocritical Sourcebook, ed. Larry Sitsky, 593-597. Westport,
Connecticut: Greenwood Press, 2002.
Cutler,
Chris. ÒA History of Plunderphonics.Ó Resonance 3, no. 2, and 4, no. 1 (May and
November 1995), http://www.l-m-c.org.uk/texts/plunder.html
(accessed May 4, 2005)
Duguid, Brian. ÒInterview with John Oswald.Ó EST issue 6 (Summer 1995),
http://
media.hyperreal.org/zines/est/intervs/oswald.html (accessed May 4, 2005)
Forte, Allen.ÒSchenkerÕs Conception
of Musical Structure.Ó Readings in Schenker
Analysis and
Other Approaches, ed. Maury Yeston. New Haven: Yale University Press,
1977.
Foucault,
Michel. The Archaeology of Knowledge. Translated by A.M. Sheridan Smith.
New
York: Pantheon Books, 1972.
Foucault,
Michel. Madness and Civilization; A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason.
Translated
by Richard Howard. New York: Pantheon Books, 1965.
Hanslick,
Eduard. The Beautiful in Music.
Translated by Gustav Cohen. New York:
The
Liberal Arts Press, 1956.
Huyssen,
Andreas. After the Great Divide:
Modernism, Mass Culture, Postmodernism.
Bloomington:
Indiana University Press, 1986.
Kivy,
Peter. Sound Sentiment:
An Essay on the Musical Emotions, Including the
Complete Text of The Corded Shell. Philadelphia: Temple University Press,
1989.
Leech-Wilkinson,
Daniel. ÒMachautÕs Rose, Lis and the Problem of Early Music
Analysis,Ó Musical
Analysis 3, No.1 (March, 1984),
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=02625245%28198403%293%3A1%3C9%3AM%2
7LATP%3E2.0.CO%3B2-8
Leech-Wilkinson,
Daniel. The Modern Invention of Medieval Music: Scholarship,
Ideology, Performance. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge
University Press, 2002.
LeMay,
Matt. review of 69 Plunderphonics 69. pitchforkmedia,
http://pitchforkmedia.com/record-reviews/o/oswald_john/69-plunderphonics-96.shtml
Marcus,
Greil. Invisible Republic: Bob DylanÕs Basement Tapes. New York: Henry Holt,
1997.
Marcus,
Greil. Lipstick Traces:
A Secret History of the Twentieth Century. Cambridge,
Massachusetts:
Harvard University Press, 1989.
McClary,
Susan. ÒConstructions of Subjectivity in SchubertÕs Music.Ó Queering the
Pitch: The New Gay and Lesbian
Musicology, ed. Philip
Brett, Elizabeth Wood,
and Gary C. Thomas. New York: Routledge,
1994.
McClary,
Susan. Conventional Wisdom: The Content of Musical Form. Berkeley:
University
of California Press, 2000.
Miller,
Paul D. (a.k.a. DJ Spooky that Subliminal Kid). Rhythm Science. Cambridge,
Massachusetts:
Mediawork/MIT Press, 2004.
Oswald,
John. ÒPlunderphonics, or Audio Piracy as a Compositional Prerogative.Ó
http://www.plunderphonics.com/xhtml/xplunder.html
(accessed May 4, 2005).
Sarig,
Roni. The Secret History of Rock: The Most Influential Bands YouÕve Never
Heard. New York: Billboard Books, 1998.
Schenker,
Heinrich. ÒOrganic Structure in Sonata Form.Ó Translated by Orin
Grossman. Readings in Schenker Analysis and
Other Approaches, ed. Maury
Yeston. New
Haven: Yale University Press, 1977.
Schoenberg,
Arnold. Style and Idea: Selected Writings of Arnold Schoenberg. Edited by
Leonard
Stein. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1984.
Sterne,
Jonathan. The Audible Past: Cultural Origins of Sound Reproduction. Durham:
Duke
University Press, 2003.
Subotnik,
Rose Rosengard. Deconstructive Variations. Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota
Press, 1996.
Swafford,
Jan. Charles Ives: A Life With Music. New York: W.W. Norton, 1996.
Tanay,
Dorit Esther. ÒÕNos faysoms contre NatureÉÕ: Fourteenth-Century Sophismata
And
the Musical Avant Garde.Ó Journal of the History of Ideas 59, No. 1 (January
1998): 29-51.
[1]
Susan
McClary, ÒConstructions of Subjectivity in SchubertÕs Music,Ó in Queering
the Pitch: The New Gay and Lesbian Musicology, ed. Philip Brett, Elizabeth Wood, and Gary C.
Thomas (New York: Routledge, 1994), 211-212.
[2]
Susan
McClary, Conventional Wisdom: The Content of Musical Form (Berkeley: University of California Press,
2000), 67.
[3] While not exactly centuries old, ÒBaby, Let Me Follow You Down,Ó an old blues, is copyrighted under the name ÒEric von Schmidt.Ó This is because Bob Dylan learned the song from him and credited it to him on his first album, Bob Dylan, Columbia Records, 1962.
[4]
Aristotle,
Politics, Book Eight, Part
V, trans. Benjamin Jowett, http://classic.mit.edu/Aristotle/politics.5.five.html
(accessed May 3, 2005).
[5]
Daniel
Leech-Wilkinson, ÒMachautÕs Rose, Lis and the Problem of Early Music Analysis,Ó Musical Analysis 3, No.1, (March, 1984),
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0262-5245%28198403%293%3A1%3C9%3AM%27LATP%3E2.0.CO%3B2-8
[6]
Allen
Forte, ÒSchenkerÕs Conception of Musical Structure,Ó from Readings in
Schenker Analysis, ed. Maury
Yeston (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977), 8.
[7] Heinrich Schenker, trans. Orin Grossman, ÒOrganic Structure in Sonata Form,Ó from Readings in Schenker Analysis, 38.
[8] Heinrich Schenker , 51.
[9]
Allen
Forte, 7.
[10]
Eduard
Hanslick, trans. Gustav Cohen, The Beautiful in Music (New York: The Liberal Arts Press, 1956), 119.
[11] Rose Rosengard Subotnik, ÒToward a Deconstruction of Structural Listening: A Critique of Schoenberg, Adorno, and Stravinsky,Ó from Deconstructive Variations (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1996).
[12] Arnold
Schoenberg, Style and Idea: Selected Writings of Arnold Schoenberg (New York: St. MartinÕs Press, 1975), 121.
[13]
John Brenkman, ÒMass Media From Collective Experience to the Culture of
Privatization,Ó Social Text (Winter 1979), 101.
[14] Theodor W. Adorno, Introduction to the Sociology of Music, trans. E.B. Ashton (New York: Seabury Press, 1976), 22-27.
[14] Theodor W. Adorno, 22.
[15] Jonathan
Sterne, The Audible Past: Cultural
Origins of Sound Reproduction (Durham: Duke University Press, 2003), 33
[16] Paul
D. Miller (a.k.a. DJ Spooky that Subliminal Kid), Rhythm Science (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Mediawork/MIT
Press, 2004), 81.
[17] AndrŽ Breton, Manifestoes of Surrealism, trans. Richard Seaver and Helen R. Lane (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1969), 268.
[18] John
Oswald, ÒPlunderphonics, or Audio Piracy as a Compositional Prerogative,Ó
http:// www.plunderphonics.com/xhtml/xplunder.html
[19] Brian Duguid, ÒInterview with John Oswald, EST issue six (Summer 1995), http://media.hyperreal.org/zines/est/intervs/oswald.html
[20] Geo. Ray Brain, ÒPlunderphonic- Album Notes,Ó http://www.plunderphonics.com/xhtml/xnotes.html
[21] For instance, Risveglio di una Citta (1914) (CD track 9)
[22] Brian Duguid.
[23] Matt Le May, http://pitchforkmedia.com/record-reviews/o/oswald_john/69-plunderphonics-96.shtml
[24] Chris
Cutler, ÒA History of Plunderphonics,Ó originally in Resonance 3, no. 2 and 4, no. 1,
http://www.l-m-c.org.uk/texts/plunder.html
[25] For instance, Lipstick Traces, or Invisible Republic
[25] Rose Subotnik,ÒToward a Deconstruction of Structural Listening: A Critique of Schoenberg, Adorno, and StravinskyÓ in Deconstructive Variations (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1996), 148-176.
[26] Rose
Rosengarad Subotnik, Deconstructive Variations, 167-68.
[27] Rose Rosengard Subotnik, 172.
[28] Asking such questions as "What is this
music's meaning?" and "Is there a way to objectively judge it?"
necessarily take us into the realm of aesthetics. While philosophy plays a role
in my theory I do not wish to place a heavy emphasis on philosophical words and
contexts that have no bearing on the matter of this specific music. Therefore,
I will attempt create new words and phrases that are free from the heavy
baggage of this weighty discipline.
[29]
Famously, Frank ZappaÕs first encounter with Varese occurred in this
manner. See Jim Cotter, ÒFrank Zappa (1940-1993)Ó from Music of the
Twentieth-Century Avant-Garde: a Biocritical Sourcebook (Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood Press, 2002),
593.